A. C. Ewing
Template:Short description Template:Use dmy dates Template:Use British English Template:Infobox philosopher Alfred Cyril Ewing Template:Post-nominals/GBR (Template:IPAc-en Template:Respell; 11 May 1899 – 14 May 1973) was an English philosopher who spent most of his career at the University of Cambridge. He was a prolific writer who made contributions to Kant scholarship, metaphysics, epistemology, ethics, and the philosophy of religion.
BiographyEdit
Alfred Ewing was born in Leicester, England, on 11 May 1899, the only child of Emma and H. F. Ewing. He was educated at Wyggeston Grammar School.<ref>{{#invoke:citation/CS1|citation |CitationClass=web }}</ref><ref name=":1">Template:Citation</ref>
From his entrance to University College, Oxford, Ewing's early academic career was, as Russell Grice remarks,Template:Efn one of "almost unparalleled brilliance."Template:Sfn Firsts in Classical Moderations and, in 1920, 'Greats' were followed by a Bishop Fraser ScholarshipTemplate:Efn at Oriel College in 1920 and a Senior Demyship at Magdalen College in 1921Template:Sfn He was awarded the John Locke Scholarship in Mental Philosophy (now the John Locke Prize) the same year.
In 1923, Ewing was amongst the first Oxford students to be awarded a DPhil,<ref>"A celebration of the DPhil Centenary 1919–2019"</ref> his (revised) thesis being published as Kant's Treatment of Causality (1924). He served as a lecturer at Oxford 1924 –1925,<ref name=":9">Template:Cite book</ref> He was awarded the Green Prize in Moral Philosophy in 1926.<ref name=":3">{{#invoke:citation/CS1|citation |CitationClass=web }}</ref> An expanded version of the essay for which he won the same was published as The Morality of Punishment (1929), with a short introduction by W. D. Ross.<ref name=":6" />
After holding temporary positions at Michigan University (in the summer session of 1926) and Armstrong College, Newcastle-upon-Tyne (in 1927), he served as a lecturer in philosophy at University College, Swansea from 1927 until 1931.<ref name=":9" />
In 1931 he was appointed University Lecturer in Moral Science at Cambridge.<ref name=":1" /> (A. J. Ayer describes him being as being 'imported' to teach the history of philosophy.)<ref name=":2" /> Ewing would later recall his "shock" on arriving at Cambridge to find "dominant not the influence of Moore, Broad, or Russell, but the influence of Wittgenstein" reporting that "the reaction his philosophy provoked in me was one of sharp antagonism."<ref>Template:Cite book</ref>
He was awarded, the Cambridge D.Litt in 1933,<ref name=":3" /> at the remarkably early age of 34.Template:Sfn The following year, Ewing published his extensive study Idealism: A Critical Survey, which was reviewed favourably by T. E. Jessop.<ref name=":7">Template:Cite journal</ref> And offers an early characterisation of a 'traditional account' of coherentist epistemic justification.<ref>Template:Citation</ref>
The late 1930s saw the publication of "Meaninglessness"<ref name="mind" /> and 'The Linguistic Theory'<ref>Template:Cite journal</ref><ref>Template:Cite journal</ref> two "powerfully argued" papers that, Brand Blanshard contends, "must have contributed much to the disintegration of positivism."<ref name=":5" />
He served as president of the Aristotelian Society from 1941 to 1942, and was elected a Fellow of the British Academy in 1941.<ref name=":3" /> He delivered the latter's annual Henriette Hertz philosophical lecture the same year.<ref name=":0">Template:Cite journal</ref><ref name=":8">Template:Cite journal</ref> During the Second World War, Goebel records, Ewing turned his attention back to ethics with the publication of a series of articles that formed the basis of two works both published in 1947:The Definition of Good (an investigation primarily into problems of metaethics) and The Individual, the State, and World Government (a work on political ethics against the background of the European catastrophe and the danger of nuclear war).Template:Sfn In a 1945 article for The Hibbert Journal he argued there were, as Brian McGuinness puts it, "no retributive, reformatory, or deterrent grounds, for making the terms of peace for Germany as a whole more severe than they would otherwise need to be".<ref name=":10">Template:Cite book</ref> Wittgenstein wrote to Rush Rhees that Ewing’s article was "stupidish and academical but not unkind. It treated the Germans as prospective inmates of a reformatory school, managed on modern, humane principles. ... the Journal surprised me as being rather human."<ref name=":10" />
Two visiting professorships took him to Princeton and Northwestern University in 1949.Template:Sfn In the winter of 1950 Ewing attended the silver jubilee Indian Philosophical Congress in Calcutta and lectured at a number of Indian universities.<ref>Template:Cite journal</ref> He returned to India in 1959, to Mysore, to attend the joint symposium between the Indian Philosophical Congress and the International Institute of Philosophy, of which he was an active member.Template:Sfn
At Cambridge where, as Ayer contends, Ewing was "not well treated," he was "eventually" made a reader in 1954.<ref name=":2" /> And, after many years of lecturing for the university, he was finally elected a fellow of Jesus College in 1962,<ref name=":2">Template:Cite book</ref> As Ayer, notes. Ewing "was an able philosopher, a good scholar and a prolific writer" but one that "never caught the idiom … largely foisted on Cambridge in the 1930s by Ludwig Wittgenstein."<ref name=":2" />
After holding a visiting position in Colorado in 1963, he retired from Cambridge in 1966 with an Honorary Fellowship from Jesus College. and moved to Manchester. But in 1967 he took a visiting position at San Francisco State CollegeTemplate:Efn and in 1971 such a post at Delaware.<ref name=":3" />
He continued to write, working to complete Value and Reality: the Philosophical Case for Theism (1973) which was published posthumously.<ref name=":4">Template:Citation</ref> This was a work, Grice records, Ewing "had started writing for twenty-five years before its publication," and one "that had been his central concern for the last five years of his life."Template:Sfn
Ewing died of a stroke in Manchester, England, on 14 May 1973. He left his papers, and Goebel reports, his body, to the University of Manchester.Template:Sfn His eyes went to Manchester Royal Eye Hospital and the rest to Manchester anatomy department.<ref>Template:Cite news</ref> To "the Moral Science Library in SIdgwick Avenue, Cambridge, he left his picture of Kant."<ref>Template:Cite news</ref>
Ayer recalls Ewing "as naive, unworldly even by academic standards, intellectually shrewd, unswervingly honest and a devout Christian."<ref>Template:Cite book</ref> Ayer also recalls teasing Ewing with the question of what he was most looking forward to in the afterlife, His immediate response being that "God will tell me whether there are synthetic a priori propositions."<ref name=":2" />
Blanshard paid tribute to Ewing in both a journal obituary, and within his own Library of Living Philosophers Festschrift.<ref>Template:Cite book</ref><ref name=":5">Template:Cite journal</ref>
Thomas Hurka notes that "Grice's fine obituary of him is poignant, describing a man whose work was not appreciated at its true worth because of a change in philosophical fashion—and the arrogance of those who made the change—and irrelevant facts about his personality" but "that as parts of moral philosophy return to views like Ewing's his contributions are becoming better known."<ref name=":4" />
Philosophical workEdit
Ewing was a defender of traditional metaphysics (as opposed to post-modern ethics) and developed what has been termed an "analytic idealism".<ref>Template:Cite book</ref>
He was one of the foremost analysts of the concept "good", and a distinguished contributor to justificatory theorizing about punishment.Template:Citation needed
Ewing was critical of the verification theory of meaning.<ref name="mind">Template:Cite journal</ref> He held the view that probability was not a quality of a thing, preferring to understand it in relative terms. Any probability statement without implicit or explicit reference to the relevant data upon which probability is based was considered meaningless.<ref name=mind/>
Additionally he viewed self-contradictions to be meaningful. He said that although there is "a sense in which it seems reasonable to say that all self-contradictory sentences are meaningless" in that we cannot "combine" the meaningful constituents of self-contradictions in thought, there is also a sense in which they are meaningful. He therefore took issue with the thesis that "we cannot think the meaning of a self-contradictory statement as a whole, though we know the meaning of the separate words". A self-contradiction, according to Ewing, proposes that two ideas can be combined into one, which is a proposition. If self-contradictions were meaningless and a "mere set of words" then we would not be able to investigate or say if they were wrong, and it is this proposition that they can be combined which makes a self-contradictory utterance meaningful.<ref name=mind/>
Ewing distinguished between two forms of philosophical analysis. The first is "what the persons who make a certain statement usually intend to assert" and the second "the qualities, relations and species of continuants mentioned in the statement". As an illustration he takes the statement "I see a tree", this statement could be analysed in terms what the everyday person intends when they say this or it could be analysed metaphysically by asserting representationalism.<ref>Template:Cite journal</ref>
WorksEdit
BooksEdit
- Kant's Treatment of Causality. London: Kegan Paul, 1924.<ref>Template:Cite journal</ref>
- The Morality of Punishment. with Suggestions for a General Theory of Ethics, London: Kegan Paul, 1929.<ref name=":6">Template:Cite journal</ref><ref>Template:Cite journal</ref> reprinted with a new preface, Montclair, N.J.: Patterson Smith, 1970
- Idealism: A Critical Survey. London: Methuen, 1934.<ref>Template:Cite journal</ref><ref name=":7" /> (New edition, 1961.)
- A Short Commentary on Kant's "Critique of Pure Reason". London: Methuen, 1938.<ref>Template:Cite journal</ref><ref>Template:Cite journal</ref> (New edition, 1950.)
- Reason and Intuition. London: Humphrey Milford, 1941.<ref name=":0" /><ref name=":8" />
- The Individual, the State, and World Government. New YorK: Macmillan, 1947.<ref>Template:Cite journal</ref><ref>Template:Cite journal</ref><ref>Template:Cite journal</ref><ref>Template:Cite journal</ref><ref>Template:Cite journal</ref>
- The Definition of Good. New York: Macmillan, 1947; London: Routledge, Kegan Paul, 1948.<ref>Template:Cite journal</ref><ref>Template:Cite journal</ref><ref>Template:Cite journal</ref><ref>Template:Cite journal</ref><ref>Template:Cite journal</ref>
- The Fundamental Questions of Philosophy. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1951.<ref>Template:Cite journal</ref><ref>Template:Cite journal</ref> (New edition, London: Routledge, 1980.)
- Ethics. London: English Universities Press, 1953. (New editions, New York: Free Press, 1965;<ref>Template:Cite journal</ref> London: Teach Yourself Books, 1975.)
- (ed.) The Idealist Tradition: from Berkeley to Blanshard; edited, with an introduction and commentary. Glencoe, Ill.: Free Press, 1957.
- Second Thoughts in Moral Philosophy. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1959.<ref>Template:Cite journal</ref><ref>Template:Cite journal</ref> (New edition, 2012.)
- Non-linguistic Philosophy. London: George Allen & Unwin, 1968.<ref>Template:Cite journal</ref><ref>Template:Cite journal</ref>
- Value and Reality: the Philosophical Case for Theism. London: George Allen & Unwin, 1973<ref>Template:Cite journal</ref><ref>Template:Cite journal</ref><ref>Template:Cite journal</ref>
Select papers/book chaptersEdit
- (1923) "Kant's Transcendental Deduction of the Categories" Mind, 32, (125): 50–66<ref>Template:Cite journal</ref>
- (1925)."The Relation Between Knowing and its Object (I.)"Mind. 34 (134): 137–153
- (1925) "The Relation Between Knowing and Its Object (II.)" Mind, 34 (135): 300–310.
- (1927) "Punishment as a Moral Agency: An Attempt to Reconcile the Retributive and the Utilitarian View" Mind 36 (143): 292–305;
- (1929) "The Idea of Cause" Journal of Philosophical Studies. 4 (16): 453–466
- (1930) "Direct Knowledge and Perception". Mind. 39 (154): 137–153.
- (1931) "The Message of Kant". Journal of Philosophical Studies. 6 (21): 43–55
- (1932) "A Defence of Causality". Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society. 33: 95–128, reprinted in Kennick, W. E. (ed.) Metaphysics: Readings and Reappraisals (1966) pp. 258–275
- (1933) "The Paradoxes of Kant's Ethics", Philosophy 21 (1933), 40-56 Template:JSTOR
- (1935) "Mechanical and Teleological Causation", Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume 14 , 67-82<ref>Template:Cite journal</ref>
- (1935) "Two Kinds of Analysis", Analysis 22(4): 60–64. Template:JSTOR
- (1937) Template:Cite journal excerpted in Edwards, Paul & Arthur Pap (eds.) A Modern Introduction to Philosophy (1965) [1957], a very much abbreviated form of this article contributed by Ewing, along with a brief 1961 addendum, can e found in MacGregor, Geddes & Robb, J. Wesley (eds) Readings in religious philosophy (1962).
- (1937) "Some Points in the Philosophy of Locke" Philosophy, 12(45), 33–46. Template:JSTOR
- (1938) "What is action?" Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume 17 <ref>Template:Cite journal</ref>
- (1939) "A Suggested Non-Naturalistic Analysis of Good" Mind 48 (1939), 1-22, Template:JSTOR reprinted in Readings in Ethical Theory, ed. Wilfrid Sellars and John Hospers (1952).
- (1939) "Intuitionism and Utilitarianism", Revue Internationale de Philosophie. 1 (4): 649–665 Template:JSTOR
- (1939). "The Linguistic Theory of "A Priori" Propositions". Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society. 40: 207–244. reprinted in: H.D. Lewis (ed.), Clarity is not enough. Essays in Criticism of Linguistic Philosophy, London 2/1969, 147-169 (abridged version);
- (1943) "Punishment as Viewed by the Philosopher" The Canadian Bar Review, 21
- (1944) "Subjectivism and Naturalism in Ethics" Mind, Vol. 53, No. 210, pp. 120–141, reprinted in: Sellars and Hospers (eds.), Readings in Ethical Theory, pp. 118–133 (1957)
- (1945) “The Ethics of Punishing Germany”, Hibbert Journal 43: 2, 99-106
- (1947) "Kantianism" in Dagobert D. Runes (ed.) Twentieth Century Philosophy: Living Schools of Thought pp. 251–264
- (1949) "Philosophical Ethics and the Ethics of Practical Life" in Proceedings of the Tenth International Congress of Philosophy 1:470–472
- (1953)."Empiricism in Ethics". Proceedings of the XIth International Congress of Philosophy 10 pp. 78–82.
- (1953) "The Necessity Of Metaphysics," in H. D. Lewis (ed.) Contemporary British Philosophy. Personal Statements. Third series
- (1954) "Kant's Attack on Metaphysics". Revue Internationale de Philosophie. 8 (30 (4)): 371–391
- (1955) "Recent Tendencies in Moral Philosophy in Great Britain" Zeitschrift Für Philosophische Forschung, vol. 9, no. 2, pp. 337–347.
- (1957) "Recent Developments in British Ethical Thought," in C. A. Mace (ed.), British Moral Philosophy in the Mid-Century, London: George Allen & Unwin, pp. 63–95.
- (1961) "The Autonomy of Ethics" in: Ian Ramsey (ed.), Prospect for Metaphysics. Essays of Metaphysical Exploration, pp. 33–49
- (1967) "Conflicts of Duty", "Kant and Kantian Ethics", "Naturalistic Ethics" and other entries in: J. Macquarrie (ed.), The Dictionary of Christian Ethics
- (1968) "The Concept of Democracy" in: World Perspectives in Philosophy, Religion, and Culture
- (1968) "C.I. Lewis on the Relation Between the Good and the Right" in Schilpp, P. A. (ed.) The Philosophy of C. I. Lewis (The Library of Living Philosophers, vol. 13). Open Court.
- (1970) "Christian Ethics and Utilitarianism" in R. L. Cunningham (ed.), Situationism and The New Morality, New York, 152–167
- (1970) "Are all a priori propositions and inferences analytic?" International Logic Review 1, 77–87
- (1971) "The problem of universals" Philosophical Quarterly 21 , 207–216
- (1971) "The Significance of Idealism for the Present Day" Idealistic Studies 1 (1971), 1–12 {{#invoke:doi|main}}
- (1973) "Common Sense Propositions" Philosophy 48 , 363–379
- (1975) "My Philosophical Attitude" in Philosophers on Their Own Work, vol. 1 (in a series published under the auspices of the International Federation of Philosophical Societies.<ref>Template:Cite book</ref>
- (1980) "Blanshard's View of Good" in Schilpp, P. A. (ed.) The Philosophy of Brand Blanshard (The Library of Living Philosophers, vol. 15).
*More complete publication details can be found online in Bernd Goebel's entry on Ewing for the BBKL.<ref>{{#invoke:citation/CS1|citation |CitationClass=web }}</ref>
NotesEdit
ReferencesEdit
SourcesEdit
- Template:Cite journal
- Template:Cite book (Introductory essay to a translation of Ewing's Ethics.)
Further readingEdit
- Binkley, Luther J., "III. A. C. Ewing: "Ought" as the Basic Ethical Term,"Template:Cite book (1961)
- R.D. Geivett, "Ewing, Alfred Cyril" in: T.A. Hart (ed.), The Dictionary of Historical Theology (2000) pp. 200–201 Template:ISBN
- Thomas Hurka (ed.), Underivative Duty: British Moral Philosophers from Sidgwick to Ewing (Oxford, 2011) Template:ISBN
- Hurka, Thomas, "Common Themes from Sidgwick to Ewing" author pre-print, published version: {{#invoke:doi|main}}
- Olson, Jonas, and Mark Timmons, 'A. C. Ewing's First and Second Thoughts in Metaethics', author pre-print, published version: {{#invoke:doi|main}}
- Olson, J. & Timmons, M. (2019). Ewing, A. C.. In International Encyclopedia of Ethics. {{#invoke:doi|main}}
- Template:Cite book
- Quinton, Anthony (1996) "Ewing, Alfred Cecil" [sic] in: Brown, Stuart C.; Collinson, Diané; Wilkinson, Robert, eds. Biographical dictionary of twentieth-century philosophers Template:ISBN pp.220–221
External linksEdit
- Brand Blanshard "Alfred Cyril Ewing, 1899–1973" (Archived),