Template:Short description Template:Infobox philosopher Jean Buridan (Template:IPAc-en;<ref>Template:Cite Collins Dictionary</ref> {{#invoke:IPA|main}}; Latin: Johannes Buridanus; Template:Circa – Template:Circa) was an influential 14thTemplate:Nbhcentury French scholastic philosopher.
Buridan taught in the faculty of arts at the University of Paris for his entire career and focused in particular on logic and on the works of Aristotle. Buridan sowed the seeds of the Copernican Revolution in Europe.<ref> Kuhn, T. The Copernican Revolution, 1958, pp. 119–123.</ref> He developed the concept of impetus, the first step toward the modern concept of inertia and an important development in the history of medieval science. His name is most familiar through the thought experiment known as Buridan's ass, but the thought experiment does not appear in his extant writings.<ref>Dugas, René. Histoire de la méchanique. 1955. Tr.: Maddox, J.R.. A History of Mechanics. Dover: NY. 1988:48. "[Pierre] Duhem, who has studied Buridan's works in detail, including those concerning free will, says that he has found no trace of the parable of the ass, which apart from his status in the history of mechanics, has made Buridan's name classical."</ref>
LifeEdit
Education and careerEdit
Buridan was born sometime before 1301, perhaps at or near the town of Béthune in Picardy, France,<ref name="Zupko 1">Zupko 2015, §1</ref> or perhaps elsewhere in the diocese of Arras.<ref> Template:Cite book</ref> He received his education in Paris, first at the Collège du Cardinal Lemoine and then at the University of Paris, receiving his Master of Arts degree and formal license to teach at the latter by the mid-1320s.<ref name="Zupko 1"/>
Unusually, he spent his entire academic life in the faculty of arts, rather than obtaining the doctorate in law, medicine or theology that typically prepared the way for a career in philosophy.<ref name="Zupko 1"/> Also unusual for a philosopher of his time, Buridan further maintained his intellectual independence by remaining a secular cleric, rather than joining a religious order. A papal letter of 1330 refers to him as simply, "clericus Atrebatensis diocoesis, magister in artibus [a cleric from the Diocese of Arras and Master of Arts]."<ref>Faral 1951, p. 11</ref> As university statutes permitted only those educated in theology to teach or write on the subject, there are no writings from Buridan on either theological matters or commentary of Peter Lombard's Sentences.<ref name="Zupko 1"/>
Speculation on his reasons for avoiding religious matters have remained uncertain.<ref>Zupko 2004, ch. 10</ref><ref>Courtenay 2002</ref><ref>Courtenay 2005</ref> Most scholars think it is unlikely that he went unnoticed, given his philosophical talents. As well, it is unlikely that he could not afford to study theology, given that he received several bursaries and stipends. Indeed, he is listed in a document from 1350 as being among the teachers capable of supporting themselves without the need for financial assistance from the University.<ref name="Zupko 1"/> John Alexander Zupko has speculated that Buridan "deliberately chose to remain among the 'artists [artistae]',"<ref name="Zupko 1"/> possibly envisioning philosophy as a secular enterprise based on what is evident to both the senses and the intellect, rather than the non-evident truths of theology revealed through scripture and doctrine.<ref name="Zupko 1"/>
The last appearance of Buridan in historical documents came in 1359, where he was mentioned as the adjudicator in a territorial dispute between the English and Picard nations.<ref name="Zupko 1"/> It is supposed that he died sometime after then, since one of his benefices was awarded to another person in 1362.<ref>Michael 1986, pp. 79–238 399–404</ref>
The bishop Albert of Saxony, himself renowned as a logician, was among the most notable of his students.Template:Citation needed
An ordinance of Louis XI of France in 1473, directed against the nominalists, prohibited the reading of his works.Template:Citation needed
Apocryphal storiesEdit
Template:Quote box Apocryphal stories abound about his reputed amorous affairs and adventures which are enough to show that he enjoyed a reputation as a glamorous and mysterious figure in Paris life.<ref>Faral 1951, p. 16</ref> None of the stories can be confirmed, and most contradict known historical information.<ref name="Faral 9-33">Faral 1951, p. 9-33</ref>
Some rumors hold that he died when the King of France had him put in a sack and thrown into the River Seine after his affair with the Queen came to light. François Villon alludes to this in his famous poem Ballade des Dames du Temps Jadis. Others suggest that he was expelled from Paris due to his nominalist teachings and moved to Vienna to found the University of Vienna. Another story talks of him hitting Pope Clement VI with a shoe.<ref name="Zupko 1"/><ref name="Faral 9-33"/>
Impetus theoryEdit
{{#invoke:Labelled list hatnote|labelledList|Main article|Main articles|Main page|Main pages}} The concept of inertia was alien to the physics of Aristotle. Aristotle, and his peripatetic followers held that a body was maintained in motion only by the action of a continuous external force. Thus, in the Aristotelian view, a projectile moving through the air would owe its continuing motion to eddies or vibrations in the surrounding medium, a phenomenon known as antiperistasis. In the absence of a proximate force, the body would come to rest almost immediately.
Buridan developed a theory of impetus by which the mover imparts to the moved a power, proportional to the speed and mass, which keeps it moving. In addition, he correctly theorized that resistance of the air progressively reduces the impetus and that weight can add or detract from speed.<ref>{{#invoke:citation/CS1|citation |CitationClass=web }}</ref>Buridan was the first to name this motion-maintaining property impetus but the theory itself probably did not originate with him. A less sophisticated notion of impressed forced can be found in the commentary of John Philoponus on Aristoteilan physics.<ref name="Zupko 6">Zupko 2015, §6</ref> In this he was possibly influenced by John Philoponus who was developing the Stoic notion of hormé (impulse).<ref name="Zupko 6"/><ref>Zupko 1997</ref> The major difference between Buridan's theory and that of his predecessor is that he rejected the view that the impetus dissipated spontaneously, instead asserting that a body would be arrested by the forces of air resistance and gravity which might be opposing its impetus. Buridan further held that the impetus of a body increased with the speed with which it was set in motion, and with its quantity of matter. This is closely related to the modern concept of momentum. Buridan saw impetus as causing the motion of the object:
- ...after leaving the arm of the thrower, the projectile would be moved by an impetus given to it by the thrower and would continue to be moved as long as the impetus remained stronger than the resistance, and would be of infinite duration were it not diminished and corrupted by a contrary force resisting it or by something inclining it to a contrary motion (Questions on Aristotle's Metaphysics XII.9: 73ra).<ref>T. F. Glick, S. J. Livesay, F. Wallis, Medieval Science, Technology and Medicine: An Encyclopedia, 2005, p. 107.</ref>
Buridan also contended that impetus is a variable quality whose force is determined by the speed and quantity of the matter in the subject. In this way, the acceleration of a falling body could be understood in terms of its gradual accumulation of units of impetus.<ref name="Zupko 6"/>
LegacyEdit
Because of his developments, historians of science Pierre Duhem<ref>Template:Cite book</ref> and Anneliese Maier<ref>Template:Cite book</ref> both saw Buridan as playing an important role in the demise of Aristotelian cosmology.<ref>Template:Cite book</ref> Duhem even called Buridan the forerunner of Galileo.<ref>Duhem 1906–13</ref> Zupko has disagreed, pointing out that Buridan did not use his theory to transform the science of mechanics, but instead remained a committed Aristotelian in thinking that motion and rest are contrary states and that the universe is finite in extent.<ref name="Zupko 6"/>
WorksEdit
{{ safesubst:#invoke:Unsubst||date=__DATE__ |$B=Template:AmboxTemplate:Main other }}
- Hughes, G. E. (1983). John Buridan on Self-Reference: Chapter Eight of Buridan's Sophismata. An edition and translation with an introduction, and philosophical commentary. Cambridge/London/New York: Cambridge University Press, Template:ISBN.
- King, Peter (1986). John Buridan's Logic: The Treatise on Supposition; The Treatise on Consequences. Translation from the Latin with a Philosophical Introduction, Dordrecht: Reidel.
- Zupko, John Alexander, ed. and tr. (1990). John Buridan's Philosophy of Mind: An Edition and Translation of Book III of His Questions on Aristotle's De Anima (Third Redaction), with Commentary and Critical and Interpretative Essays. Doctoral dissertation, Cornell University.
- Klima, Gyula, tr. (2002). John Buridan: 'Summulae de Dialectica'. Yale Library of Medieval Philosophy. New Haven, Conn./London: Yale University Press.
- John Buridan (2015). Treatise on Consequences, translated, with an Introduction by Stephen Read. New York: Fordham University Press.
- Klima, G., Sobol, P. G., Hartman, P., & Zupko, J. (2023, May 31). John Buridan’s Questions on Aristotle’s de Anima – Iohannis Buridani Quaestiones in Aristotelis de Anima (Vol. 9). Springer.
See alsoEdit
ReferencesEdit
NotesEdit
SourcesEdit
- Template:Cite book
- Template:Cite journal
- Template:Cite journal
- Template:Cite book
- Template:Cite book
- Template:Cite journal
- Template:Cite book
- {{#invoke:citation/CS1|citation
|CitationClass=web }}
Further readingEdit
- Klima, Gyula (2009). John Buridan. New York: Oxford University Press.
- Template:Cite journal
- Thijssen, J. M. M. H., and Jack Zupko (ed.) (2002). The Metaphysics and Natural Philosophy of John Buridan Leiden: Brill.
External linksEdit
- Template:Cite SEP
- Bibliography by Fabienne Pironet (up to 2001)
- Buridan's Logic and Metaphysics: an annotated bibliography (updates the bibliography of Fabienne Pironet to 2014)
- Buridan's Logical Works. I. An Overview of the Summulae de dialectica a detailed summary of the nine treatises of the Summulae de dialectica
- Buridan's Logical Works. II. The Treatise on Consequences and other writings a summary of the other logical writings
- Buridan: Editions, Translations and Studies on the Manuscript Tradition Complete bibliography of the logical and metaphysical works
{{#invoke:Navbox|navbox}} Template:Authority control