Template:Short description Template:Infobox mathematical statement Template:Transformation rules

In classical logic, disjunctive syllogism<ref>Template:Cite book</ref><ref>Template:Cite book</ref> (historically known as modus tollendo ponens (MTP),<ref>Lemmon, Edward John. 2001. Beginning Logic. Taylor and Francis/CRC Press, p. 61.</ref> Latin for "mode that affirms by denying")<ref>Template:Cite book</ref> is a valid argument form which is a syllogism having a disjunctive statement for one of its premises.<ref>Hurley</ref><ref>Copi and Cohen</ref>

An example in English:

  1. I will choose soup or I will choose salad.
  2. I will not choose soup.
  3. Therefore, I will choose salad.

Propositional logicEdit

In propositional logic, disjunctive syllogism (also known as disjunction elimination and or elimination, or abbreviated ∨E),<ref>Sanford, David Hawley. 2003. If P, Then Q: Conditionals and the Foundations of Reasoning. London, UK: Routledge: 39</ref><ref>Hurley</ref><ref>Copi and Cohen</ref><ref>Moore and Parker</ref> is a valid rule of inference. If it is known that at least one of two statements is true, and that it is not the former that is true; we can infer that it has to be the latter that is true. Equivalently, if P is true or Q is true and P is false, then Q is true. The name "disjunctive syllogism" derives from its being a syllogism, a three-step argument, and the use of a logical disjunction (any "or" statement.) For example, "P or Q" is a disjunction, where P and Q are called the statement's disjuncts. The rule makes it possible to eliminate a disjunction from a logical proof. It is the rule that

<math>\frac{P \lor Q, \neg P}{\therefore Q}</math>

where the rule is that whenever instances of "<math>P \lor Q</math>", and "<math>\neg P</math>" appear on lines of a proof, "<math>Q</math>" can be placed on a subsequent line.

Disjunctive syllogism is closely related and similar to hypothetical syllogism, which is another rule of inference involving a syllogism. It is also related to the law of noncontradiction, one of the three traditional laws of thought.

Formal notationEdit

For a logical system that validates it, the disjunctive syllogism may be written in sequent notation as

<math> P \lor Q, \lnot P \vdash Q </math>

where <math>\vdash</math> is a metalogical symbol meaning that <math>Q</math> is a syntactic consequence of <math>P \lor Q</math>, and <math>\lnot P</math>.

It may be expressed as a truth-functional tautology or theorem in the object language of propositional logic as

<math> ((P \lor Q) \land \neg P) \to Q</math>

where <math>P</math>, and <math>Q</math> are propositions expressed in some formal system.

Natural language examplesEdit

Here is an example:

  1. It is red or it is blue.
  2. It is not blue.
  3. Therefore, it is red.

Here is another example:

  1. The breach is a safety violation, or it is not subject to fines.
  2. The breach is not a safety violation.
  3. Therefore, it is not subject to fines.

Strong formEdit

Modus tollendo ponens can be made stronger by using exclusive disjunction instead of inclusive disjunction as a premise:

<math>\frac{P \underline\lor Q, \neg P}{\therefore Q}</math>

Related argument formsEdit

Unlike modus ponens and modus ponendo tollens, with which it should not be confused, disjunctive syllogism is often not made an explicit rule or axiom of logical systems, as the above arguments can be proven with a combination of reductio ad absurdum and disjunction elimination.

Other forms of syllogism include:

Disjunctive syllogism holds in classical propositional logic and intuitionistic logic, but not in some paraconsistent logics.<ref>Chris Mortensen, Inconsistent Mathematics, Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, First published Tue Jul 2, 1996; substantive revision Thu Jul 31, 2008</ref>

See alsoEdit

ReferencesEdit

Template:Reflist