In modal logic, Sahlqvist formulas are a certain kind of modal formula with remarkable properties. The Sahlqvist correspondence theorem states that every Sahlqvist formula is canonical, and corresponds to a class of Kripke frames definable by a first-order formula.
Sahlqvist's definition characterizes a decidable set of modal formulas with first-order correspondents. Since it is undecidable, by Chagrova's theorem, whether an arbitrary modal formula has a first-order correspondent, there are formulas with first-order frame conditions that are not Sahlqvist [Chagrova 1991] (see the examples below). Hence Sahlqvist formulas define only a (decidable) subset of modal formulas with first-order correspondents.
DefinitionEdit
Sahlqvist formulas are built up from implications, where the consequent is positive and the antecedent is of a restricted form.
- A boxed atom is a propositional atom preceded by a number (possibly 0) of boxes, i.e. a formula of the form <math>\Box\cdots\Box p</math> (often abbreviated as <math>\Box^i p</math> for <math>0 \leq i < \omega</math>).
- A Sahlqvist antecedent is a formula constructed using ∧, ∨, and <math>\Diamond</math> from boxed atoms, and negative formulas (including the constants ⊥, ⊤).
- A Sahlqvist implication is a formula A → B, where A is a Sahlqvist antecedent, and B is a positive formula.
- A Sahlqvist formula is constructed from Sahlqvist implications using ∧ and <math>\Box</math> (unrestricted), and using ∨ on formulas with no common variables.
Examples of Sahlqvist formulasEdit
- <math>p \rightarrow \Diamond p</math>
- Its first-order corresponding formula is <math>\forall x \; Rxx</math>, and it defines all reflexive frames
- <math>p \rightarrow \Box\Diamond p</math>
- Its first-order corresponding formula is <math>\forall x \forall y [Rxy \rightarrow Ryx]</math>, and it defines all symmetric frames
- <math>\Diamond \Diamond p \rightarrow \Diamond p</math> or <math>\Box p \rightarrow \Box \Box p</math>
- Its first-order corresponding formula is <math>\forall x \forall y \forall z [(Rxy \land Ryz) \rightarrow Rxz]</math>, and it defines all transitive frames
- <math>\Diamond p \rightarrow \Diamond \Diamond p</math> or <math>\Box \Box p \rightarrow \Box p</math>
- Its first-order corresponding formula is <math>\forall x \forall y [Rxy \rightarrow \exists z (Rxz \land Rzy)]</math>, and it defines all dense frames
- <math>\Box p \rightarrow \Diamond p</math>
- Its first-order corresponding formula is <math>\forall x \exists y \; Rxy</math>, and it defines all right-unbounded frames (also called serial)
- <math>\Diamond\Box p \rightarrow \Box\Diamond p</math>
- Its first-order corresponding formula is <math>\forall x \forall x_1 \forall z_0 [Rxx_1 \land Rxz_0 \rightarrow \exists z_1 (Rx_1z_1 \land Rz_0z_1)]</math>, and it is the Church–Rosser property.
Examples of non-Sahlqvist formulasEdit
- <math>\Box\Diamond p \rightarrow \Diamond \Box p</math>
- This is the McKinsey formula; it does not have a first-order frame condition.
- <math>\Box(\Box p \rightarrow p) \rightarrow \Box p</math>
- The Löb axiom is not Sahlqvist; again, it does not have a first-order frame condition.
- <math>(\Box\Diamond p \rightarrow \Diamond \Box p) \land (\Diamond\Diamond q \rightarrow \Diamond q)</math>
- The conjunction of the McKinsey formula and the (4) axiom has a first-order frame condition (the conjunction of the transitivity property with the property <math> \forall x[\forall y(Rxy \rightarrow \exists z[Ryz]) \rightarrow \exists y(Rxy \wedge \forall z[Ryz \rightarrow z = y])] </math>) but is not equivalent to any Sahlqvist formula.
Kracht's theoremEdit
When a Sahlqvist formula is used as an axiom in a normal modal logic, the logic is guaranteed to be complete with respect to the basic elementary class of frames the axiom defines. This result comes from the Sahlqvist completeness theorem [Modal Logic, Blackburn et al., Theorem 4.42]. But there is also a converse theorem, namely a theorem that states which first-order conditions are the correspondents of Sahlqvist formulas. Kracht's theorem states that any Sahlqvist formula locally corresponds to a Kracht formula; and conversely, every Kracht formula is a local first-order correspondent of some Sahlqvist formula which can be effectively obtained from the Kracht formula [Modal Logic, Blackburn et al., Theorem 3.59].
ReferencesEdit
- Patrick Blackburn, Maarten de Rijke, Yde Venema, 2010. Modal logic (4. print. with corr.). Cambridge Univ. Press.
- L. A. Chagrova, 1991. An undecidable problem in correspondence theory. Journal of Symbolic Logic 56:1261–1272.
- Marcus Kracht, 1993. How completeness and correspondence theory got married. In de Rijke, editor, Diamonds and Defaults, pages 175–214. Kluwer.
- Henrik Sahlqvist, 1975. Correspondence and completeness in the first- and second-order semantics for modal logic. In Proceedings of the Third Scandinavian Logic Symposium. North-Holland, Amsterdam.