Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Gibbard–Satterthwaite theorem
(section)
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
{{Short description|Impossibility result for ranked-choice voting systems}}{{Expert needed|game theory | date = June 2024 | reason = inadequate description of theorem and practical importance }} {{Use dmy dates|date=August 2017}}The '''Gibbard–Satterthwaite theorem''' is a theorem in [[social choice theory]]. It was first conjectured by the philosopher [[Michael Dummett]] and the mathematician [[Robin Farquharson]] in 1961<ref>{{cite journal|author=Rudolf Farra and Maurice Salles|title=An Interview with Michael Dummett: From analytical philosophy to voting analysis and beyond|journal=Social Choice and Welfare|volume=27|issue=2|date=October 2006|doi=10.1007/s00355-006-0128-9|pages=347–364|s2cid=46164353|url=http://eprints.lse.ac.uk/552/1/VPP05_01.pdf}}</ref> and then proved independently by the philosopher [[Allan Gibbard]] in 1973<ref name="gibbard">{{cite journal |first=Allan |last=Gibbard |author-link=Allan Gibbard |title=Manipulation of voting schemes: A general result |journal=Econometrica |volume=41 |issue=4 |year=1973 |pages=587–601 |jstor=1914083 |doi=10.2307/1914083 }}</ref> and economist [[Mark Satterthwaite]] in 1975.<ref name="satterthwaite">{{cite journal |first=Mark Allen |last=Satterthwaite |author-link=Mark Satterthwaite |title=Strategy-proofness and Arrow's conditions: Existence and correspondence theorems for voting procedures and social welfare functions |journal=Journal of Economic Theory |volume=10 |issue=2 |date=April 1975 |pages=187–217 |doi=10.1016/0022-0531(75)90050-2 |citeseerx=10.1.1.471.9842 }}</ref> It deals with deterministic [[Ranked voting|ordinal electoral system]]s that choose a single winner, and shows that for every voting rule of this form, at least one of the following three things must hold: # The rule is dictatorial, i.e. there exists a distinguished voter who can choose the winner; or # The rule limits the possible outcomes to two alternatives only; or # The rule is not straightforward, i.e. there is no single [[Strategic dominance|always-best strategy]] (one that does not depend on other voters' preferences or behavior). [[Gibbard's theorem|Gibbard's proof of the theorem]] is more general and covers processes of collective decision that may not be ordinal, such as [[cardinal voting]].{{NoteTag|Gibbard's theorem does not imply that cardinal methods necessarily incentivize reversing one's relative rank of two candidates.}} [[Gibbard's 1978 theorem]] and [[Hylland's theorem]] are even more general and extend these results to non-deterministic processes, where the outcome may depend partly on chance; the [[Duggan–Schwartz theorem]] extends these results to multiwinner electoral systems.
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)