Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Problem of multiple generality
(section)
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
{{Short description|Failure in traditional logic to describe certain intuitively valid inferences}} The '''problem of multiple generality''' names a failure in [[term logic|traditional logic]] to describe [[validity (logic)|valid]] inferences that involves multiple [[Quantifiers (logic)|quantifiers]]. For example, it is intuitively clear that if: :''Some cat is feared by every mouse'' then it follows logically that: :''All mice are afraid of at least one cat''. The syntax of [[traditional logic]] (TL) permits exactly one quantifier, i.e. there are four sentence types: "All A's are B's", "No A's are B's", "Some A's are B's" and "Some A's are not B's". Since the sentences above each contain two quantifiers ('some' and 'every' in the first sentence and 'all' and 'at least one' in the second sentence), they cannot be adequately represented in TL. The best TL can do is to incorporate the second quantifier from each sentence into the second term, thus rendering the artificial-sounding terms 'feared-by-every-mouse' and 'afraid-of-at-least-one-cat'. This in effect "buries" these quantifiers, which are essential to the inference's validity, within the hyphenated terms. Hence the sentence "Some cat is feared by every mouse" is allotted the same [[logical form]] as the sentence "Some cat is hungry". And so the logical form in TL is: :''Some A's are B's'' :''All C's are D's'' which is clearly invalid. The first logical calculus capable of dealing with such inferences was [[Gottlob Frege]]'s ''[[Begriffsschrift]]'' (1879), the ancestor of modern [[first-order logic|predicate logic]], which dealt with quantifiers by means of variable bindings. Modestly, Frege did not argue that his logic was more expressive than extant logical calculi, but commentators on Frege's logic regard this as one of his key achievements. Using modern [[first-order logic|predicate calculus]], we quickly discover that the statement is ambiguous. :''Some cat is feared by every mouse'' could mean ''(Some cat is feared) by every mouse'' (paraphrasable as ''Every mouse fears some cat''), i.e. :''For every mouse m, there exists a cat c, such that c is feared by m,'' :<math>\forall m \, (\, \text{Mouse}(m) \rightarrow \exists c \, (\text{Cat}(c) \land \text{Fears}(m,c)) \, )</math> in which case the conclusion is trivial. But it could also mean ''Some cat is (feared by every mouse)'' (paraphrasable as '' There's a cat feared by all mice''), i.e. :''There exists one cat c, such that for every mouse m, c is feared by m.'' :<math>\exists c \, ( \, \text{Cat}(c) \land \forall m \, (\text{Mouse}(m) \rightarrow \text{Fears}(m,c)) \, )</math> This example illustrates the importance of specifying the [[Scope (logic)#Quantifiers|scope]] of such quantifiers as ''for all'' and ''there exists''.
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)