Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Relevance logic
(section)
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
{{Short description|A kind of non-classical logic}} '''Relevance logic''', also called '''relevant logic''', is a kind of [[non-classical logic]] requiring the [[Antecedent (logic)|antecedent]] and [[consequent]] of [[Entailment|implications]] to be relevantly related. They may be viewed as a family of [[substructural logic|substructural]] or [[modal logic|modal]] logics. It is generally, but not universally, called ''relevant logic'' by British and, especially, Australian [[logician]]s, and ''relevance logic'' by American logicians. Relevance logic aims to capture aspects of implication that are ignored by the "[[material conditional|material implication]]" operator in classical [[truth-functional logic]], namely the notion of relevance between antecedent and conditional of a true implication. This idea is not new: [[C. I. Lewis]] was led to invent modal logic, and specifically [[strict implication]], on the grounds that classical logic grants [[paradoxes of material implication]] such as the principle that [[Vacuous truth|a falsehood implies any proposition]].<ref>Lewis, C. I. (1912). "Implication and the Algebra of Logic." ''[[Mind (journal)|Mind]]'', '''21'''(84):522β531.</ref><ref>Lewis, C. I. (1917). "The issues concerning material implication." ''Journal of Philosophy, Psychology, and Scientific Methods'', '''14''':350β356.</ref> Hence "if I'm a donkey, then two and two is four" is true when translated as a material implication, yet it seems intuitively false since a true implication must tie the antecedent and consequent together by some notion of relevance. And whether or not the speaker is a donkey seems in no way relevant to whether two and two is four. In terms of a syntactical constraint for a [[propositional calculus]], it is necessary, but not sufficient, that premises and conclusion share [[atomic formula]]e (formulae that do not contain any [[logical connective]]s). In a [[predicate calculus]], relevance requires sharing of variables and constants between premises and conclusion. This can be ensured (along with stronger conditions) by, e.g., placing certain restrictions on the rules of a natural deduction system. In particular, a Fitch-style [[natural deduction]] can be adapted to accommodate relevance by introducing tags at the end of each line of an application of an inference indicating the premises relevant to the conclusion of the inference. [[Gentzen]]-style [[sequent calculus|sequent calculi]] can be modified by removing the weakening rules that allow for the introduction of arbitrary formulae on the right or left side of the [[sequent]]s. A notable feature of relevance logics is that they are [[paraconsistent logic]]s: the existence of a contradiction will not necessarily cause an "[[principle of explosion|explosion]]." This follows from the fact that a conditional with a contradictory antecedent that does not share any propositional or predicate letters with the consequent cannot be true (or derivable).
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)