Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Syllogism
(section)
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
{{Short description|Type of logical argument that applies deductive reasoning}} {{Redirect|Epagoge|the genus of moth|Epagoge (moth)}} {{Redirect|Minor premise|the 2020 thriller film|Minor Premise (film){{!}}''Minor Premise'' (film)}} {{Multiple issues|{{More citations needed|date=February 2023}}{{Essay-like|date=February 2023}}}} A '''syllogism''' ({{langx|grc|συλλογισμός}}, ''syllogismos'', 'conclusion, inference') is a kind of [[Argument|logical argument]] that applies [[deductive reasoning]] to arrive at a [[Logical consequence|conclusion]] based on two [[proposition]]s that are asserted or assumed to be true. [[File:Socrates_Louvre.jpg|thumb|"Socrates" at the Louvre]] In its earliest form (defined by [[Aristotle]] in his 350 BC book ''[[Prior Analytics]]''), a deductive syllogism arises when two true premises (propositions or statements) validly imply a conclusion, or the main point that the argument aims to get across.<ref>{{Cite book|last=Lundberg|first=Christian|title=The Essential Guide to Rhetoric|publisher=Bedford/St.Martin's|year=2018|pages=38}}</ref> For example, knowing that all men are mortal (major premise), and that [[Socrates]] is a man (minor premise), we may validly conclude that Socrates is mortal. Syllogistic arguments are usually represented in a three-line form: <blockquote><poem>All men are mortal. Socrates is a man. Therefore, Socrates is mortal.<ref>John Stuart Mill, ''A System of Logic, Ratiocinative and Inductive, Being a Connected View of the Principles of Evidence, and the Methods of Scientific Investigation'', 3rd ed., vol. 1, chap. 2 (London: John W. Parker, 1851), 190.</ref></poem></blockquote>In antiquity, two rival syllogistic theories existed: [[Term logic|Aristotelian syllogism]] and [[Stoic logic|Stoic syllogism]].<ref name=":0" /> From the [[Middle Ages]] onwards, ''categorical syllogism'' and ''syllogism'' were usually used interchangeably. This article is concerned only with this historical use. The syllogism was at the core of historical deductive reasoning, whereby facts are determined by combining existing statements, in contrast to [[inductive reasoning]], in which facts are predicted by repeated observations. Within some academic contexts, syllogism has been superseded by [[First-order logic|first-order predicate logic]] following the work of [[Gottlob Frege]], in particular his ''[[Begriffsschrift]]'' (''Concept Script''; 1879). Syllogism, being a method of valid logical reasoning, will always be useful in most circumstances, and for general-audience introductions to logic and clear-thinking.<ref>Hurley, Patrick J. 2011. ''A Concise Introduction to Logic''. Cengage Learning. {{ISBN|9780840034175}}</ref><ref>Zegarelli, Mark. 2010. ''Logic for Dummies''. John Wiley & Sons. {{ISBN|9781118053072}}.</ref>
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)