Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Arrow–Debreu model
(section)
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
== Formal statement == {{blockquote|The contents of both theorems [fundamental theorems of welfare economics] are old beliefs in economics. Arrow and Debreu have recently treated this question with techniques permitting proofs.|Gérard Debreu|Valuation equilibrium and Pareto optimum (1954)|source=}}{{blockquote|This statement is precisely correct; once there were beliefs, now there was knowledge. The Arrow-Debreu model, as communicated in the Theory of Value, changed basic thinking and quickly became the standard model of price theory. It is the "benchmark” model in Finance, International Trade, Public Finance, Transportation, and even macroeconomics... In rather short order, it was no longer "as it is" in Marshall, Hicks, and Samuelson; rather, it became "as it is" in Theory of Value.|Hugo Sonnenschein|remarks at the Debreu conference, Berkeley, 2005|source=}} This section follows the presentation in,<ref name=":1">{{Cite book |last=Starr |first=Ross M. |title=General Equilibrium Theory: An Introduction |publisher=Cambridge University Press |year=2011 |isbn=978-0521533867 |edition=2 |pages= |at=}}</ref> which is based on.<ref>Arrow, K. J. (1962). "Lectures on the theory of competitive equilibrium." Unpublished notes of lectures presented at Northwestern University.</ref> === Intuitive description of the Arrow–Debreu model === The Arrow–Debreu model models an economy as a combination of three kinds of agents: the households, the producers, and the market. The households and producers transact with the market but not with each other directly. The households possess endowments (bundles of commodities they begin with), one may think of as "inheritance." For mathematical clarity, all households must sell all their endowment to the market at the beginning. If they wish to retain some of the endowments, they would have to repurchase them from the market later. The endowments may be working hours, land use, tons of corn, etc. The households possess proportional ownerships of producers, which can be thought of as [[joint-stock companies]]. The profit made by producer <math>j</math> is divided among the households in proportion to how much stock each household holds for the producer <math>j</math>. Ownership is imposed initially, and the households may not sell, buy, create, or discard them. The households receive a budget, income from selling endowments, and [[dividend]] from producer profits. The households possess preferences over bundles of commodities, which, under the assumptions given, makes them [[Utility maximization problem|utility maximizers]]. The households choose the consumption plan with the highest utility they can afford using their budget. The producers can transform bundles of commodities into other bundles of commodities. The producers have no separate utility functions. Instead, they are all purely profit maximizers. The market is only capable of "choosing" a market price vector, which is a list of prices for each commodity, which every producer and household takes (there is no bargaining behavior—every producer and household is a [[price taker]]). The market has no utility or profit. Instead, the market aims to choose a market price vector such that, even though each household and producer is maximizing their utility and profit, their consumption and production plans "harmonize." That is, "[[Market clearing|the market clears]]". In other words, the market is playing the role of a "[[Walrasian auctioneer]]." {| class="wikitable" |+How an Arrow–Debreu model moves from beginning to end. !households !producers |- |receive endowment and ownership of producers | |- |sell all endowment to the market | |- | |plan production to maximize profit |- | |enter purchase agreements between the market and each other |- | |perform production plan |- | |sell everything to the market |- | |send all profits to households in proportion to ownership |- |plan consumption to maximize utility under budget constraint | |- |buy the planned consumption from the market | |} === Notation setup === In general, we write indices of agents as superscripts and vector coordinate indices as subscripts. ==== useful notations for real vectors ==== * <math>x \succeq y</math> if <math>\forall n, x_n \geq y_n</math> * <math>\R^N_+</math> is the set of <math>x</math> such that <math>x \succeq 0</math> * <math>\R_{++}^N</math> is the set of <math>x</math> such that <math>x \succ 0</math> * <math>\Delta_N = \left\{x\in \R^N: x_1, ..., x_N \geq 0, \sum_{n\in 1:N} x_n = 1\right\}</math> is the [[Simplex|N-simplex]]. We often call it the '''price simplex''' since we sometimes scale the price vector to lie on it. ==== market ==== * The '''commodities''' are indexed as <math>n\in 1:N</math>. Here <math>N</math> is the number of commodities in the economy. It is a finite number. * The '''price vector''' <math>p = (p_1, ..., p_N) \in \R_{++}^N</math> is a vector of length <math>N</math>, with each coordinate being the price of a commodity. The prices may be zero or positive. ==== households ==== * The '''households''' are indexed as <math>i\in I</math>. * Each household begins with an '''endowment''' of commodities <math>r^i\in \R^N_+</math>. * Each household begins with a tuple of '''ownerships''' of the producers <math>\alpha^{i,j} \geq 0</math>. The ownerships satisfy <math>\sum_{i\in I} \alpha^{i,j} = 1 \quad \forall j\in J </math>. * The budget that the household receives is the sum of its income from selling endowments at the market price, plus profits from its ownership of producers:<math display="block">M^i(p) = \langle p, r^i\rangle + \sum_{j\in J}\alpha^{i,j}\Pi^j(p)</math>(<math>M</math> stands for ''money'') * Each household has a '''Consumption Possibility Set''' <math>CPS^i\subset \R_+^N</math>. * Each household has a '''preference relation''' <math>\succeq^i</math> over <math>CPS^i</math>. * With assumptions on <math>\succeq^i</math> (given in the next section), each preference relation is representable by a '''utility function''' <math>u^i: CPS^i \to [0, 1]</math> by the [[Debreu theorems]]. Thus instead of maximizing preference, we can equivalently state that the household is maximizing its utility. * A '''consumption plan''' is a vector in <math>CPS^i</math>, written as <math>x^i</math>. * <math>U_+^i(x^i)</math> is the set of consumption plans at least as preferable as <math>x^i</math>. * The '''budget set''' is the set of consumption plans that it can afford:<math display="block">B^i(p) = \{x^i \in CPS^i : \langle p, x^i \rangle \leq M^i(p)\}</math>. * For each price vector <math>p</math>, the household has a '''demand''' vector for commodities, as <math>D^i(p)\in \R_+^N</math>. This function is defined as the solution to a constraint maximization problem. It depends on both the economy and the initial distribution.<math display="block">D^i(p) := \arg\max_{x^i \in B^i(p)} u^i(x^i)</math>It may not be well-defined for all <math>p \in \R^N_{++}</math>. However, we will use enough assumptions to be well-defined at equilibrium price vectors. ==== producers ==== * The producers are indexed as <math>j\in J</math>. * Each producer has a '''Production Possibility Set''' <math>PPS^j</math>. Note that the supply vector may have both positive and negative coordinates. For example, <math>(-1, 1, 0)</math> indicates a production plan that uses up 1 unit of commodity 1 to produce 1 unit of commodity 2. * A '''production plan''' is a vector in <math>PPS^j</math>, written as <math>y^j</math>. * For each price vector <math>p</math>, the producer has a '''supply''' vector for commodities, as <math>S^j(p)\in \R^N</math>. This function will be defined as the solution to a constraint maximization problem. It depends on both the economy and the initial distribution.<math display="block">S^j(p) := \arg\max_{y^j\in PPS^j} \langle p, y^j\rangle</math>It may not be well-defined for all <math>p \in \R^N_{++}</math>. However, we will use enough assumptions to be well-defined at equilibrium price vectors. * The '''profit''' is <math display="block">\Pi^j(p) := \langle p, S^j(p)\rangle = \max_{y^j\in PPS^j} \langle p, y^j\rangle</math> ==== aggregates ==== * aggregate consumption possibility set <math>CPS = \sum_{i\in I}CPS^i</math>. * aggregate production possibility set <math>PPS = \sum_{j\in J}PPS^j</math>. * aggregate endowment <math>r = \sum_i r^i</math> * aggregate demand <math>D(p) := \sum_i D^i(p)</math> * aggregate supply <math>S(p) := \sum_j S^j(p)</math> * excess demand <math>Z(p) = D(p) - S(p) - r</math> ==== the whole economy ==== * An '''economy''' is a tuple <math>(N, I, J, CPS^i, \succeq^i, PPS^j)</math>. It is a tuple specifying the commodities, consumer preferences, consumption possibility sets, and producers' production possibility sets. * An '''economy with initial distribution''' is an economy, along with an initial distribution tuple <math>(r^i, \alpha^{i,j})_{i\in I, j\in J}</math> for the economy. * A '''state''' of the economy is a tuple of price, consumption plans, and production plans for each household and producer: <math>((p_n)_{n\in 1:N}, (x^i)_{i\in I}, (y^j)_{j\in J})</math>. * A state is '''feasible''' iff each <math>x^i \in CPS^i</math>, each <math>y^j\in PPS^j</math>, and <math>\sum_{i\in I}x^i \preceq \sum_{j\in J}y^j + r</math>. * The feasible production possibilities set, given endowment <math>r</math>, is <math>PPS_r := \{y\in PPS: y+r \succeq 0\}</math>. * Given an economy with distribution, the '''state corresponding to a price vector''' <math>p</math> is <math>(p, (D^i(p))_{i\in I}, (S^j(p))_{j\in J})</math>. * Given an economy with distribution, a price vector <math>p</math> is an '''equilibrium price vector''' for the economy with initial distribution, iff<math display="block">Z(p)_n \begin{cases} \leq 0 \text{ if } p_n = 0 \\ = 0 \text{ if } p_n > 0 \end{cases}</math>That is, if a commodity is not free, then supply exactly equals demand, and if a commodity is free, then supply is equal or greater than demand (we allow free commodity to be oversupplied). * A state is an '''equilibrium state''' iff it is the state corresponding to an equilibrium price vector. === Assumptions === {| class="wikitable" |+on the households !assumption !explanation !can we relax it? |- | <math>CPS^i </math> is closed |Technical assumption necessary for proofs to work. |No. It is necessary for the existence of demand functions. |- |local nonsatiation: <math>\forall x\in CPS^i, \epsilon > 0, </math> <math>\exists x'\in CPS^i, x' \succ^i x,\|x' - x\|< \epsilon </math> |Households always want to consume a little more. |No. It is necessary for Walras's law to hold. |- | <math>CPS^i </math> is strictly convex |strictly [[diminishing marginal utility]] |Yes, to mere convexity, with Kakutani's fixed-point theorem. See next section. |- | <math>CPS^i </math> is convex |diminishing marginal utility |Yes, to nonconvexity, with [[Shapley–Folkman lemma]]. |- |continuity: <math>U_+^i(x^i)</math> is closed. |Technical assumption necessary for the existence of utility functions by the [[Debreu theorems]]. |No. If the preference is not continuous, then the excess demand function may not be continuous. |- | <math>U_+^i(x^i)</math> is strictly convex. |For two consumption bundles, any bundle between them is better than the lesser. |Yes, to mere convexity, with Kakutani's fixed-point theorem. See the next section. |- | <math>U_+^i(x^i)</math> is convex. |For two consumption bundles, any bundle between them is no worse than the lesser. |Yes, to nonconvexity, with [[Shapley–Folkman lemma]]. |- |The household always has at least one feasible consumption plan. |no bankruptcy |No. It is necessary for the existence of demand functions. |} {| class="wikitable" |+on the producers !assumption !explanation !can we relax it? |- | <math>PPS^j </math> is strictly convex |[[diseconomies of scale]] |Yes, to mere convexity, with Kakutani's fixed-point theorem. See next section. |- | <math>PPS^j </math> is convex |no [[economies of scale]] |Yes, to nonconvexity, with [[Shapley–Folkman lemma]]. |- | <math>PPS^j </math> contains 0. |Producers can close down for free. | |- | <math>PPS^j </math> is a closed set |Technical assumption necessary for proofs to work. |No. It is necessary for the existence of supply functions. |- | <math>PPS \cap \R_+^N </math> is bounded |There is no arbitrarily large "free lunch". |No. Economy needs scarcity. |- | <math>PPS \cap (-PPS) </math> is bounded |The economy cannot reverse arbitrarily large transformations. | |} === Imposing an artificial restriction === The functions <math> D^i(p), S^j(p)</math> are not necessarily well-defined for all price vectors <math>p</math>. For example, if producer 1 is capable of transforming <math>t</math> units of commodity 1 into <math>\sqrt{(t+1)^2-1}</math> units of commodity 2, and we have <math>p_1 / p_2 < 1</math>, then the producer can create plans with infinite profit, thus <math>\Pi^j(p) = +\infty</math>, and <math>S^j(p)</math> is undefined. Consequently, we define "'''restricted market'''" to be the same market, except there is a universal upper bound <math>C</math>, such that every producer is required to use a production plan <math>\|y^j\| \leq C</math>. Each household is required to use a consumption plan <math>\|x^i\| \leq C</math>. Denote the corresponding quantities on the restricted market with a tilde. So, for example, <math>\tilde Z(p)</math> is the excess demand function on the restricted market.<ref>The restricted market technique is described in (Starr 2011), Section 18.2. The technique was used in the original publication by Arrow and Debreu (1954).</ref> <math>C</math> is chosen to be "large enough" for the economy so that the restriction is not in effect under equilibrium conditions (see next section). In detail, <math>C</math> is chosen to be large enough such that: * For any consumption plan <math>x</math> such that <math>x \succeq 0, \|x\| = C</math>, the plan is so "extravagant" that even if all the producers coordinate, they would still fall short of meeting the demand. * For any list of production plans for the economy <math>(y^j\in PPS^j)_{j\in J}</math>, if <math>\sum_{j\in J} y^j + r \succeq 0</math>, then <math>\|y^j\| < C</math>for each <math>j\in J</math>. In other words, for any attainable production plan under the given endowment <math>r</math>, each producer's individual production plan must lie strictly within the restriction. Each requirement is satisfiable. * Define the set of '''attainable aggregate production plans''' to be <math>PPS_r = \left\{\sum_{j\in J} y^j : y^j \in PPS^j \text{ for each } j\in J, \text{ and }\sum_{j\in J} y^j + r \succeq 0\right\}</math>, then under the assumptions for the producers given above (especially the "no arbitrarily large free lunch" assumption), <math>PPS_r</math> is bounded for any <math>r \succeq 0</math> (proof omitted). Thus the first requirement is satisfiable. * Define the set of '''attainable individual production plans''' to be <math>PPS_r^j := \{y^j \in PPS^j: y^j\text{ is a part of some attainable production plan under endowment }r\}</math>then under the assumptions for the producers given above (especially the "no arbitrarily large transformations" assumption), <math>PPS_r^j</math> is bounded for any <math>j\in J, r \succeq 0</math> (proof omitted). Thus the second requirement is satisfiable. The two requirements together imply that the restriction is not a real restriction when the production plans and consumption plans are "[[Interior solution (optimization)|interior]]" to the restriction. * At any price vector <math>p</math>, if <math>\|\tilde S^j(p)\| < C</math>, then <math>S^j(p) </math> exists and is equal to <math>\tilde S^j(p) </math>. In other words, if the production plan of a restricted producer is interior to the artificial restriction, then the unrestricted producer would choose the same production plan. This is proved by exploiting the second requirement on <math>C</math>. * If all <math>S^j(p) = \tilde S^j(p)</math>, then the restricted and unrestricted households have the same budget. Now, if we also have <math>\|\tilde D^i(p)\| < C</math>, then <math>D^i(p) </math> exists and is equal to <math>\tilde D^i(p) </math>. In other words, if the consumption plan of a restricted household is interior to the artificial restriction, then the unrestricted household would choose the same consumption plan. This is proved by exploiting the first requirement on <math>C</math>. These two propositions imply that equilibria for the restricted market are equilibria for the unrestricted market:{{Math theorem | name = Theorem | note = | math_statement =If <math>p</math> is an equilibrium price vector for the restricted market, then it is also an equilibrium price vector for the unrestricted market. Furthermore, we have <math>\tilde D^i(p) = D^i(p), \tilde S^j(p) = S^j(p)</math>. }} === existence of general equilibrium === As the last piece of the construction, we define '''[[Walras's law]]''': * The unrestricted market satisfies Walras's law at <math>p</math> iff all <math>S^j(p), D^i(p)</math> are defined, and <math> \langle p, Z(p)\rangle = 0</math>, that is,<math display="block"> \sum_{j\in J} \langle p,S^j(p)\rangle + \langle p, r\rangle = \sum_{i\in I} \langle p, D^i(p)\rangle</math> * The restricted market satisfies Walras's law at <math>p</math> iff <math> \langle p, \tilde Z(p)\rangle = 0</math>. Walras's law can be interpreted on both sides: * On the side of the households, it is said that the aggregate household expenditure is equal to aggregate profit and aggregate income from selling endowments. In other words, every household spends its entire budget. * On the side of the producers, it is saying that the aggregate profit plus the aggregate cost equals the aggregate revenue. {{Math theorem | name = Theorem | note = | math_statement = <math>\tilde Z</math> satisfies ''weak'' Walras's law: For all <math>p \in \R_{++}^N</math>, <math display="block">\langle p, \tilde Z(p)\rangle \leq 0</math> and if <math>\langle p, \tilde Z(p)\rangle < 0</math>, then <math>\tilde Z(p)_n > 0</math> for some <math>n</math>. }} {{Math proof|title=Proof sketch|proof= If total excess demand value is exactly zero, then every household has spent all their budget. Else, some household is restricted to spend only part of their budget. Therefore, that household's consumption bundle is on the boundary of the restriction, that is, <math>\|\tilde D^i(p)\| = C</math>. We have chosen (in the previous section) <math>C</math> to be so large that even if all the producers coordinate, they would still fall short of meeting the demand. Consequently there exists some commodity <math>n</math> such that <math>\tilde D^i(p)_n > \tilde S(p)_n + r_n</math> }} {{Math theorem | name = Theorem | note = | math_statement = An equilibrium price vector exists for the restricted market, at which point the restricted market satisfies Walras's law. }} {{Math proof|title=Proof sketch|proof= By definition of equilibrium, if <math>p</math> is an equilibrium price vector for the restricted market, then at that point, the restricted market satisfies Walras's law. <math>\tilde Z</math> is continuous since all <math>\tilde S^j, \tilde D^i</math> are continuous. Define a function <math display="block">f(p) = \frac{\max(0, p + \gamma \tilde Z(p))}{\sum_n \max(0, p_n + \gamma \tilde Z(p)_n)}</math>on the price simplex, where <math>\gamma</math> is a fixed positive constant. By the weak Walras law, this function is well-defined. By Brouwer's fixed-point theorem, it has a fixed point. By the weak Walras law, this fixed point is a market equilibrium. }} Note that the above proof does not give an iterative algorithm for finding any equilibrium, as there is no guarantee that the function <math>f</math> is a [[Contraction mapping|contraction]]. This is unsurprising, as there is no guarantee (without further assumptions) that any market equilibrium is a stable equilibrium. {{Math theorem | name = Corollary | note = | math_statement = An equilibrium price vector exists for the unrestricted market, at which point the unrestricted market satisfies Walras's law. }} === The role of convexity === [[Image:Unit circle.svg|thumb|right|alt=Picture of the unit circle|A quarter turn of the convex [[unit disk]] leaves the point ''(0,0)'' fixed but moves every point on the non–convex [[unit circle]].]] {{Main|Kakutani fixed-point theorem}} {{See also|Convex set|Compact set|Continuous function|Fixed-point theorem|Brouwer fixed-point theorem}} In 1954, [[Lionel McKenzie|McKenzie]] and the pair [[Kenneth Arrow|Arrow]] and [[Gérard Debreu|Debreu]] independently proved the existence of general equilibria by invoking the [[Kakutani fixed-point theorem]] on the [[fixed-point theorem|fixed point]]s of a [[hemicontinuity|continuous]] [[multivalued function|function]] from a [[compact space|compact]], convex set into itself<!-- Links to Kakutani's theorem are accurate, but the article description gives the simpler case Brouwer fixed point theorem for a point-valued function. -->. In the Arrow–Debreu approach, convexity is essential, because such fixed-point theorems are inapplicable to non-convex sets. For example, the rotation of the [[unit circle]] by 90 degrees lacks fixed points, although this rotation is a continuous transformation of a compact set into itself; although compact, the unit circle is non-convex. In contrast, the same rotation applied to the [[unit disk|convex hull of the unit circle]] leaves the point ''(0,0)'' fixed. Notice that the Kakutani theorem does not assert that there exists exactly one fixed point. Reflecting the unit disk across the y-axis leaves a vertical segment fixed, so that this reflection has an infinite number of fixed points. ===Non-convexity in large economies=== {{See also|Shapley–Folkman lemma|Market failure}} The assumption of convexity precluded many applications, which were discussed in the ''[[Journal of Political Economy]]'' from 1959 to 1961 by Francis M. Bator, [[Michael James Farrell|M. J. Farrell]], [[Tjalling Koopmans|Tjalling Koopmans]], and Thomas J. Rothenberg<!-- Starr's citation mis-spells "T." as "J." -->.<ref name="s69">{{citation | last = Starr | first = Ross M. | author-link = Ross Starr | issue = 1 | journal = Econometrica | pages = 25–38 | title = Quasi–equilibria in markets with non–convex preferences (Appendix 2: The Shapley–Folkman theorem, pp. 35–37) | volume = 37 | year = 1969 | jstor=1909201 | doi=10.2307/1909201 | citeseerx = 10.1.1.297.8498 }}.</ref> {{harvs|first=Ross M.|last=Starr|authorlink=Ross Starr|year=1969|txt}} proved the existence of [[general equilibrium theory#Nonconvexities in large economies|economic equilibria]] when some [[convex preferences|consumer preferences]] need not be [[convex set|convex]].<ref name="s69"/> In his paper, Starr proved that a "convexified" economy has general equilibria that are closely approximated by "quasi-equilbria" of the original economy; Starr's proof used the [[Shapley–Folkman lemma|Shapley–Folkman theorem]].<ref name="Starr08" >{{cite book|last=Starr|first= Ross M.|author-link=Ross Starr|chapter=Shapley–Folkman theorem|title=The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics|editor1-first=Steven N.|editor1-last=Durlauf|editor2-first=Lawrence E.|editor2-last=Blume|publisher=Palgrave Macmillan|year=2008|edition=Second|volume=4|pages=317–318 |chapter-url=http://www.dictionaryofeconomics.com/article?id=pde2008_S000107|doi=10.1057/9780230226203.1518|isbn= 978-0-333-78676-5}}</ref> === Uzawa equivalence theorem === ([[Hirofumi Uzawa|Uzawa]], 1962)<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Uzawa |first=Hirofumi |date=1962 |title=Walras' Existence Theorem and Brouwer's Fixed-Point Theorem |url=https://www.jstage.jst.go.jp/article/economics1950/13/1/13_1_59/_article/-char/ja/ |journal=季刊 理論経済学 |volume=13 |issue=1 |pages=59–62 |doi=10.11398/economics1950.13.1_59}}</ref> showed that the existence of general equilibrium in an economy characterized by a continuous excess demand function fulfilling Walras's Law is equivalent to Brouwer fixed-Point theorem. Thus, the use of Brouwer's fixed-point theorem is essential for showing that the equilibrium exists in general.<ref>(Starr 2011), Section 18.4</ref> === [[Fundamental theorems of welfare economics]] === In welfare economics, one possible concern is finding a [[Pareto efficiency|Pareto-optimal]] plan for the economy. Intuitively, one can consider the problem of welfare economics to be the problem faced by a master planner for the whole economy: given starting endowment <math>r</math> for the entire society, the planner must pick a feasible master plan of production and consumption plans <math>((x^i)_{i\in I}, (y^j)_{j\in J})</math>. The master planner has a wide freedom in choosing the master plan, but any reasonable planner should agree that, if someone's utility can be increased, while everyone else's is not decreased, then it is a better plan. That is, the Pareto ordering should be followed. Define the '''Pareto ordering''' on the set of all plans <math>((x^i)_{i\in I}, (y^j)_{j\in J})</math> by <math>((x^i)_{i\in I}, (y^j)_{j\in J}) \succeq((x'^i)_{i\in I}, (y'^j)_{j\in J})</math> iff <math>x^i \succeq^i x'^i</math> for all <math>i\in I</math>. Then, we say that a plan is Pareto-efficient with respect to a starting endowment <math>r</math>, iff it is feasible, and there does not exist another feasible plan that is strictly better in Pareto ordering. In general, there are a whole continuum of Pareto-efficient plans for each starting endowment <math>r</math>. With the set up, we have two fundamental theorems of welfare economics:<ref>(Starr 2011), Chapter 19</ref> {{Math theorem|name=First fundamental theorem of welfare economics|note=|math_statement= Any market equilibrium state is Pareto-efficient.}} {{Math proof|title=Proof sketch|proof= The price hyperplane separates the attainable productions and the Pareto-better consumptions. That is, the hyperplane <math>\langle p^*, q\rangle = \langle p^*, D(p^*)\rangle</math> separates <math>r + PPS_r</math> and <math>U_{++}</math>, where <math>U_{++}</math> is the set of all <math>\sum_{i\in I} x'^i</math>, such that <math>\forall i\in I, x'^i\in CPS^i, x'^i \succeq^i x^i</math>, and <math>\exists i\in I, x'^i \succ^i x^i</math>. That is, it is the set of aggregates of all possible consumption plans that are strictly Pareto-better. The attainable productions are on the lower side of the price hyperplane, while the Pareto-better consumptions are ''strictly'' on the upper side of the price hyperplane. Thus any Pareto-better plan is not attainable. * Any Pareto-better consumption plan must cost at least as much for every household, and cost more for at least one household. * Any attainable production plan must profit at most as much for every producer. }} {{Math theorem | name = Second fundamental theorem of welfare economics | note = | math_statement = For any total endowment <math>r</math>, and any Pareto-efficient state achievable using that endowment, there exists a distribution of endowments <math>\{r^i\}_{i\in I}</math> and private ownerships <math>\{\alpha^{i,j}\}_{i\in I, j\in J}</math> of the producers, such that the given state is a market equilibrium state for some price vector <math>p\in \R_{++}^N</math>. }}Proof idea: any Pareto-optimal consumption plan is [[Hyperplane separation theorem|separated by a hyperplane]] from the set of attainable consumption plans. The slope of the hyperplane would be the equilibrium prices. Verify that under such prices, each producer and household would find the given state optimal. Verify that Walras's law holds, and so the expenditures match income plus profit, and so it is possible to provide each household with exactly the necessary budget. {{Math proof|title=Proof|proof= Since the state is attainable, we have <math>\sum_{i\in I}x^i \preceq \sum_{j\in J}y^j + r</math>. The equality does not necessarily hold, so we define the set of attainable aggregate consumptions <math>V := \{r + y - z: y \in PPS, z \succeq 0\}</math>. Any aggregate consumption bundle in <math>V</math> is attainable, and any outside is not. Find the market price <math>p</math>. : Define <math>U_{++}</math> to be the set of all <math>\sum_{i\in I} x'^i</math>, such that <math>\forall i\in I, x'^i\in CPS^i, x'^i \succeq^i x^i</math>, and <math>\exists i\in I, x'^i \succ^i x^i</math>. That is, it is the set of aggregates of all possible consumption plans that are strictly Pareto-better. Since each <math>CPS^i</math> is convex, and each preference is convex, the set <math>U_{++}</math> is also convex. : Now, since the state is Pareto-optimal, the set <math>U_{++}</math> must be unattainable with the given endowment. That is, <math>U_{++}</math> is disjoint from <math>V</math>. Since both sets are convex, there exists a separating hyperplane between them. : Let the hyperplane be defined by <math>\langle p, q\rangle = c</math>, where <math>p\in \R^N, p\neq 0</math>, and <math>c= \sum_{i\in I}\langle p, x^i\rangle</math>. The sign is chosen such that <math>\langle p, U_{++}\rangle \geq c</math> and <math>\langle p, r+PPS\rangle \leq c</math>. Claim: <math>p \succ 0</math>. : Suppose not, then there exists some <math>n\in 1:N</math> such that <math>p_n <0</math>. Then <math>\langle p, r + 0 - k e_n\rangle > c</math> if <math>k</math> is large enough, but we also have <math>r + 0 - k e_n\in V</math>, contradiction. We have by construction <math>\langle p, \sum_{i\in I}x^i\rangle = c</math>, and <math>\langle p, V\rangle \leq c</math>. Now we claim: <math>\langle p, U_{++}\rangle > c</math>. : For each household <math>i</math>, let <math>U_+^i(x^i)</math> be the set of consumption plans for <math>i</math> that are at least as good as <math>x^i</math>, and <math>U_{++}^i(x^i)</math> be the set of consumption plans for <math>i</math> that are strictly better than <math>x^i</math>. : By local nonsatiation of <math>\succeq^i</math>, the closed half-space <math>\langle p, q\rangle \geq \langle p, x^i\rangle</math> contains <math>U_+^i(x^i)</math>. : By continuity of <math>\succeq^i</math>, the open half-space <math>\langle p, q\rangle > \langle p, x^i\rangle</math> contains <math>U_{++}^i(x^i)</math>. : Adding them up, we find that the open half-space <math>\langle p, q\rangle > c</math> contains <math>U_{++}</math>. Claim (Walras's law): <math>\langle p, r + \sum_j y^j\rangle =c =\langle p, \sum_i x^i\rangle</math> : Since the production is attainable, we have <math>r + \sum_j y^j \succeq \sum_i x^i</math>, and since <math>p\succ 0</math>, we have <math>\langle p, r + \sum_j y^j\rangle \geq \langle p, \sum_i x^i\rangle</math>. : By construction of the separating hyperplane, we also have <math>\langle p, r + \sum_j y^j\rangle \leq c =\langle p, \sum_i x^i\rangle</math>, thus we have an equality. Claim: at price <math>p</math>, each producer <math>j</math> maximizes profit at <math>y^j</math>, : If there exists some production plan <math>y'^j</math> such that one producer can reach higher profit <math>\langle p, y'^j\rangle > \langle p, y^j\rangle</math>, then : <math display="block">\langle p, r\rangle+ \sum_{j\in J}\langle p, y'^j\rangle >\langle p, r\rangle+ \sum_{j\in J}\langle p, y^j\rangle = c</math> : but then we would have a point in <math>r+PPS</math> on the other side of the separating hyperplane, violating our construction. Claim: at price <math>p</math> and budget <math>\langle p, x^i\rangle</math>, household <math>i</math> maximizes utility at <math>x^i</math>. : Otherwise, there exists some <math>x'^i</math> such that <math>x'^i \succ^i x^i</math> and <math>\langle p, x'^i\rangle \leq \langle p, x^i\rangle</math>. Then, consider aggregate consumption bundle <math>q' := \sum_{i'\in I, i' \neq i}x^i + x'^i</math>. It is in <math>U_{++}</math>, but also satisfies <math>\langle p, q'\rangle \leq \sum \langle p, x^i\rangle = c</math>. But this contradicts previous claim that <math>\langle p, U_{++}\rangle > c</math>. By Walras's law, the aggregate endowment income and profit exactly equals aggregate expenditure. It remains to distribute them such that each household <math>i</math> obtains exactly <math>\langle p, x^i\rangle</math> as its budget. This is trivial. : Here is a greedy algorithm to do it: first distribute all endowment of commodity 1 to household 1. If household 1 can reach its budget before distributing all of it, then move on to household 2. Otherwise, start distributing all endowment of commodity 2, etc. Similarly for ownerships of producers. }} === convexity vs strict convexity === The assumptions of strict convexity can be relaxed to convexity. This modification changes supply and demand functions from point-valued functions into set-valued functions (or "correspondences"), and the application of Brouwer's fixed-point theorem into Kakutani's fixed-point theorem. This modification is similar to the generalization of the [[minimax theorem]] to the existence of [[Nash equilibrium|Nash equilibria]]. The two fundamental theorems of welfare economics holds without modification. {| class="wikitable" |+converting from strict convexity to convexity !strictly convex case !convex case |- |<math>PPS^j</math> is strictly convex |<math>PPS^j</math> is convex |- |<math>CPS^i</math> is strictly convex |<math>CPS^i</math> is convex |- |<math>\succeq^i</math> is strictly convex |<math>\succeq^i</math> is convex |- |<math>\tilde S^j(p)</math> is point-valued |<math>\tilde S^j(p)</math> is set-valued |- |<math>\tilde S^j(p)</math> is continuous |<math>\tilde S^j(p)</math> has [[Hemicontinuity#Closed graph theorem|closed graph]] ("upper hemicontinuous") |- |<math>\langle p, \tilde Z(p)\rangle\leq 0</math> |<math>\langle p, z\rangle\leq 0</math> for any <math>z\in \tilde Z(p)</math> |- |... |... |- | equilibrium exists by Brouwer's fixed-point theorem | equilibrium exists by Kakutani's fixed-point theorem |} === equilibrium vs "quasi-equilibrium" === The definition of market equilibrium assumes that every household performs utility maximization, subject to budget constraints. That is, <math display="block">\begin{cases} \max_{x^i} u^i(x^i) \\ \langle p, x^i\rangle \leq M^i(p) \end{cases}</math>The dual problem would be cost minimization subject to utility constraints. That is,<math display="block">\begin{cases} u^i(x^i) \geq u^i_0\\ \min_{x^i} \langle p, x^i\rangle \end{cases}</math>for some real number <math>u^i_0</math>. The [[duality gap]] between the two problems is nonnegative, and may be positive. Consequently, some authors study the dual problem and the properties of its "quasi-equilibrium"<ref>{{Cite book |last=Debreu |first=Gerard |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=QkX10epC46cC |title=Theory of Value: An Axiomatic Analysis of Economic Equilibrium |date=1959-01-01 |publisher=Yale University Press |isbn=978-0-300-01559-1 |language=en}}</ref> (or "compensated equilibrium"<ref name=":2">{{Cite book |last=Arrow |first=Kenneth J. |url=http://worldcat.org/oclc/817224321 |title=General competitive analysis |date=2007 |publisher=North-Holland |isbn=978-0-444-85497-1 |pages= |oclc=817224321}}</ref>). Every equilibrium is a quasi-equilibrium, but the converse is not necessarily true.<ref name=":2" />
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)