Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
History of topos theory
(section)
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
==In the school of Grothendieck== During the latter part of the 1950s, the foundations of [[algebraic geometry]] were being rewritten; and it is here that the origins of the '''topos''' concept are to be found. At that time the [[Weil conjectures]] were an outstanding motivation to research. As we now know, the route towards their proof, and other advances, lay in the construction of [[étale cohomology]]. With the benefit of hindsight, it can be said that algebraic geometry had been wrestling with two problems for a long time. The first was to do with its '''''points''''': back in the days of [[projective geometry]] it was clear that the absence of 'enough' points on an [[algebraic variety]] was a barrier to having a good geometric theory (in which it was somewhat like a [[Compact space|compact]] [[manifold]]). There was also the difficulty, that was clear as soon as [[topology]] took form in the first half of the twentieth century, that the topology of algebraic varieties had 'too few' open sets. The question of points was close to resolution by 1950; [[Alexander Grothendieck]] took a sweeping step (invoking the [[Yoneda lemma]]) that disposed of it—naturally at a cost, that every variety or more general ''[[scheme (mathematics)|scheme]]'' should become a [[functor]]. It wasn't possible to ''add'' open sets, though. The way forward was otherwise. The topos definition first appeared somewhat obliquely, in or about 1960. General problems of so-called '[[descent (category theory)|descent]]' in algebraic geometry were considered, at the same period when the [[fundamental group]] was generalised to the algebraic geometry setting (as a [[pro-finite group]]). In the light of later work (c. 1970), 'descent' is part of the theory of [[comonad]]s; here we can see one way in which the Grothendieck school bifurcates in its approach from the 'pure' category theorists, a theme that is important for the understanding of how the topos concept was later treated. There was perhaps a more direct route available: the [[abelian category]] concept had been introduced by Grothendieck in his foundational work on [[homological algebra]], to unify categories of [[sheaf (mathematics)|sheaves]] of abelian groups, and of [[module (mathematics)|modules]]. An abelian category is supposed to be closed under certain category-theoretic operations—by using this kind of definition one can focus entirely on structure, saying nothing at all about the nature of the objects involved. This type of definition can be traced back, in one line, to the [[lattice (order)|lattice]] concept of the 1930s. It was a possible question to ask, around 1957, for a purely category-theoretic characterisation of categories of [[sheaf (mathematics)|sheaves]] of ''sets'', the case of sheaves of abelian groups having been subsumed by Grothendieck's work (the [[Tohoku paper|''Tôhoku'' paper]]). Such a definition of a topos was eventually given five years later, around 1962, by Grothendieck and [[Jean-Louis Verdier|Verdier]] (see Verdier's [[Nicolas Bourbaki]] seminar ''Analysis Situs''). The characterisation was by means of categories 'with enough [[colimit]]s', and applied to what is now called a [[Grothendieck topos]]. The theory was rounded out by establishing that a Grothendieck topos was a category of sheaves, where now the word ''sheaf'' had acquired an extended meaning, since it involved a [[Grothendieck topology]]. The idea of a Grothendieck topology (also known as a ''site'') has been characterised by [[John Tate (mathematician)|John Tate]] as a bold pun on the two senses of [[Riemann surface]].{{Citation needed|date=July 2017}} Technically speaking it enabled the construction of the sought-after étale cohomology (as well as other refined theories such as [[flat cohomology]] and [[crystalline cohomology]]). At this point—about 1964—the developments powered by algebraic geometry had largely run their course. The 'open set' discussion had effectively been summed up in the conclusion that varieties had a rich enough ''site'' of open sets in [[Ramification (mathematics)|unramified]] covers of their (ordinary) [[Zariski topology|Zariski-open sets]].
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)