Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Lattice (order)
(section)
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
== Definition == A lattice can be defined either order-theoretically as a partially ordered set, or as an algebraic structure. === As partially ordered set === A [[partially ordered set]] (poset) <math>(L, \leq)</math> is called a '''lattice''' if it is both a join- and a meet-[[semilattice]], i.e. each two-element subset <math>\{ a, b \} \subseteq L</math> has a [[Join (mathematics)|join]] (i.e. least upper bound, denoted by <math>a \vee b</math>) and [[Duality (order theory)|dually]] a [[Meet (mathematics)|meet]] (i.e. greatest lower bound, denoted by <math>a \wedge b</math>). This definition makes <math>\,\wedge\,</math> and <math>\,\vee\,</math> [[binary operation]]s. Both operations are monotone with respect to the given order: <math>a_1 \leq a_2</math> and <math>b_1 \leq b_2</math> implies that <math>a_1 \vee b_1 \leq a_2 \vee b_2</math> and <math>a_1 \wedge b_1 \leq a_2 \wedge b_2.</math> It follows by an [[Mathematical induction|induction]] argument that every non-empty finite subset of a lattice has a least upper bound and a greatest lower bound. With additional assumptions, further conclusions may be possible; see ''[[Completeness (order theory)]]'' for more discussion of this subject. That article also discusses how one may rephrase the above definition in terms of the existence of suitable [[Galois connection]]s between related partially ordered sets—an approach of special interest for the [[category theoretic]] approach to lattices, and for [[formal concept analysis]]. Given a subset of a lattice, <math>H \subseteq L,</math> meet and join restrict to [[partial function]]s – they are undefined if their value is not in the subset <math>H.</math> The resulting structure on <math>H</math> is called a '''{{visible anchor|partial lattice}}'''. In addition to this extrinsic definition as a subset of some other algebraic structure (a lattice), a partial lattice can also be intrinsically defined as a set with two partial binary operations satisfying certain axioms.{{sfn|Grätzer|2003|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=SoGLVCPuOz0C&pg=PA52 52]}} === As algebraic structure === A '''lattice''' is an [[algebraic structure]] <math>(L, \vee, \wedge)</math>, consisting of a set <math>L</math> and two binary, commutative and associative [[Operation (mathematics)|operations]] <math>\vee</math> and <math>\wedge</math> on <math>L</math> satisfying the following axiomatic identities for all elements <math>a, b \in L</math> (sometimes called {{em|absorption laws}}): <math display=block>a \vee (a \wedge b) = a</math> <math display=block>a \wedge (a \vee b) = a</math> The following two identities are also usually regarded as axioms, even though they follow from the two absorption laws taken together.<ref>{{harvnb|Birkhoff|1948|p=[https://archive.org/details/in.ernet.dli.2015.166886/page/n35/mode/2up 18]}}. "since <math>a = a \vee (a \wedge (a \vee a)) = a \vee a</math> and dually". Birkhoff attributes this to {{harvnb|Dedekind|1897|p=[https://publikationsserver.tu-braunschweig.de/servlets/MCRFileNodeServlet/dbbs_derivate_00006737/V.C.1596.pdf#page=10 8]}}</ref> These are called {{em|idempotent laws}}. <math display=block>a \vee a = a</math> <math display=block>a \wedge a = a</math> These axioms assert that both <math>(L, \vee)</math> and <math>(L, \wedge)</math> are [[semilattice]]s. The absorption laws, the only axioms above in which both meet and join appear, distinguish a lattice from an arbitrary pair of semilattice structures and assure that the two semilattices interact appropriately. In particular, each semilattice is the [[Duality (order theory)|dual]] of the other. The absorption laws can be viewed as a requirement that the meet and join semilattices define the same [[partial order]]. === Connection between the two definitions === An order-theoretic lattice gives rise to the two binary operations <math>\vee</math> and <math>\wedge.</math> Since the commutative, associative and absorption laws can easily be verified for these operations, they make <math>(L, \vee, \wedge)</math> into a lattice in the algebraic sense. The converse is also true. Given an algebraically defined lattice <math>(L, \vee, \wedge),</math> one can define a partial order <math>\leq</math> on <math>L</math> by setting <math display=block>a \leq b \text{ if } a = a \wedge b, \text{ or }</math> <math display=block>a \leq b \text{ if } b = a \vee b,</math> for all elements <math>a, b \in L.</math> The laws of absorption ensure that both definitions are equivalent: <math display=block>a = a \wedge b \text{ implies } b = b \vee (b \wedge a) = (a \wedge b) \vee b = a \vee b</math> and dually for the other direction. One can now check that the relation <math>\le</math> introduced in this way defines a partial ordering within which binary meets and joins are given through the original operations <math>\vee</math> and <math>\wedge.</math> Since the two definitions of a lattice are equivalent, one may freely invoke aspects of either definition in any way that suits the purpose at hand.
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)