Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Naturalistic fallacy
(section)
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
==Common uses== ===The is–ought problem=== {{Main|Is–ought problem}} The term ''naturalistic fallacy'' is sometimes used to label the problematic inference of an ''ought'' from an ''is'' (the [[is–ought problem]]).<ref>W. H. Bruening, "Moore on 'Is-Ought'," ''Ethics'' 81 (January 1971): 143–49.</ref> Michael Ridge relevantly elaborates that "[t]he intuitive idea is that evaluative conclusions require at least one evaluative premise—purely factual premises about the naturalistic features of things do not entail or even support evaluative conclusions."<ref name = "sep" /> This problematic inference usually takes the form of saying that if people generally ''do'' something (e.g., eat three times a day, smoke cigarettes, dress warmly in cold weather), then people ''ought to'' do that thing. The naturalistic fallacy occurs when the is–ought inference ("People eat three times a day, so it is morally good for people to eat three times a day") is justified by the claim that whatever practice exists is a natural one ("because eating three times a day is pleasant and desirable"). [[Jeremy Bentham|Bentham]], in discussing the relations of law and morality, found that when people discuss problems and issues they talk about how they wish it would be, instead of how it actually is. This can be seen in discussions of [[natural law]] and [[positive law]]. Bentham criticized natural law theory because in his view it was an instance of the naturalistic fallacy, claiming that it described how things are rather than how they ought to be. ===Moore's discussion=== [[Image:Principia Ethica title page.png|thumb|right|200px|The title page of ''Principia Ethica'']] According to [[G. E. Moore]]'s ''[[Principia Ethica]]'', when philosophers try to define ''good'' reductively, in terms of natural properties like ''pleasant'' or ''desirable'', they are committing the naturalistic fallacy. {{Blockquote|...the assumption that because some quality or combination of qualities invariably and necessarily accompanies the quality of goodness, or is invariably and necessarily accompanied by it, or both, this quality or combination of qualities is identical with goodness. If, for example, it is believed that whatever is pleasant is and must be good, or that whatever is good is and must be pleasant, or both, it is committing the naturalistic fallacy to infer from this that goodness and pleasantness are one and the same quality. The naturalistic fallacy is the assumption that because the words 'good' and, say, 'pleasant' necessarily describe the same objects, they must attribute the same quality to them.<ref>[[Arthur Prior|Prior, Arthur N.]] (1949), [http://www.utilitarian.org/texts/prior.html#intro Chapter 1] of ''Logic And The Basis Of Ethics'', [[Oxford University Press]] ({{ISBN|0-19-824157-7}})</ref>|[[Arthur N. Prior]]|''Logic And The Basis Of Ethics''}} In defense of [[ethical non-naturalism]] against [[ethical naturalism]], Moore's argument is concerned with the [[semantic]] and metaphysical underpinnings of ethics. Moore argues that good, in the sense of [[intrinsic value (ethics)|intrinsic value]], is simply ineffable. It cannot be defined because it is not reducible to other properties, being "one of those innumerable objects of thought which are themselves incapable of definition, because they are the ultimate terms by reference to which whatever 'is' capable of definition must be defined".<ref>Moore, G.E. [http://fair-use.org/g-e-moore/principia-ethica/s.10#s10p1 ''Principia Ethica'' § 10 ¶ 1]</ref> On the other hand, ethical naturalists eschew such principles in favor of a more empirically accessible [[analysis (philosophy)|analysis]] of what it means to be good: for example, in terms of pleasure in the context of [[hedonism]]. {{quotation|That "pleased" does not mean "having the sensation of red", or anything else whatever, does not prevent us from understanding what it does mean. It is enough for us to know that "pleased" does mean "having the sensation of pleasure", and though pleasure is absolutely indefinable, though pleasure is pleasure and nothing else whatever, yet we feel no difficulty in saying that we are pleased. The reason is, of course, that when I say "I am pleased", I do not mean that "I" am the same thing as "having pleasure". And similarly no difficulty need be found in my saying that "pleasure is good" and yet not meaning that "pleasure" is the same thing as "good", that pleasure ''means'' good, and that good ''means'' pleasure. If I were to imagine that when I said "I am pleased", I meant that I was exactly the same thing as "pleased", I should not indeed call that a naturalistic fallacy, although it would be the same fallacy as I have called naturalistic with reference to Ethics.|G. E. Moore|[http://fair-use.org/g-e-moore/principia-ethica/s.12 ''Principia Ethica'' § 12]}} In §7, Moore argues that a property is either a complex of simple properties, or else it is irreducibly simple. Complex properties can be defined in terms of their constituent parts but a simple property lacks parts. In addition to ''good'' and ''pleasure'', Moore suggests that colour [[qualia]] are undefined: if one wants to understand yellow, one must see examples of it. It will do no good to read the dictionary and learn that ''yellow'' names the colour of egg yolks and ripe lemons, or that ''yellow'' names the primary colour between green and orange on the spectrum, or that the perception of yellow is stimulated by electromagnetic radiation with a wavelength of between 570 and 590 nanometers, because yellow is all that and more, by the [[open question argument]]. ===Appeal to nature=== {{Main|Appeal to nature}} Some people use the phrase, ''naturalistic fallacy'' or ''[[appeal to nature]]'', in a different sense, to characterize inferences of the form "Something is natural; therefore, it is morally acceptable" or "This property is unnatural; therefore, this property is undesirable." Such inferences are common in discussions of [[medicine]], [[homosexuality]], [[environmentalism]], and [[veganism]]. {{quote|The naturalistic fallacy is the idea that what is found in nature is good. It was the basis for [[social Darwinism]], the belief that helping the poor and sick would get in the way of evolution, which depends on the survival of the fittest. Today, biologists denounce the naturalistic fallacy because they want to describe the natural world honestly, without people deriving morals about how we ought to behave (as in: If birds and beasts engage in adultery, infanticide, cannibalism, it must be OK).|sign = [[Steven Pinker]]<ref name="Pinker">{{Cite web|title = Q&A: Steven Pinker of 'Blank Slate'|url = http://www.upi.com/Odd_News/2002/10/30/QA-Steven-Pinker-of-Blank-Slate/26021035991232/|website = [[UPI]]|access-date = December 5, 2015|date = October 30, 2002|last = Sailer|first = Steve|archive-date = December 5, 2015|url-status = live|archive-url = https://web.archive.org/web/20151205074319/http://www.upi.com/Odd_News/2002/10/30/QA-Steven-Pinker-of-Blank-Slate/26021035991232/}}</ref>}}
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)