Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Proof theory
(section)
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
==History== Although the formalisation of logic was much advanced by the work of such figures as [[Gottlob Frege]], [[Giuseppe Peano]], [[Bertrand Russell]], and [[Richard Dedekind]], the story of modern proof theory is often seen as being established by [[David Hilbert]], who initiated what is called [[Hilbert's program]] in the [[Grundlagen der Mathematik|''Foundations of Mathematics'']]. The central idea of this program was that if we could give [[finitary]] proofs of consistency for all the sophisticated formal theories needed by mathematicians, then we could ground these theories by means of a metamathematical argument, which shows that all of their purely universal assertions (more technically their provable [[arithmetical hierarchy|<math>\Pi^0_1</math> sentences]]) are finitarily true; once so grounded we do not care about the non-finitary meaning of their existential theorems, regarding these as pseudo-meaningful stipulations of the existence of ideal entities. The failure of the program was induced by [[Kurt Gödel]]'s [[Gödel's incompleteness theorems|incompleteness theorems]], which showed that any [[ω-consistent theory]] that is sufficiently strong to express certain simple arithmetic truths, cannot prove its own consistency, which on Gödel's formulation is a <math>\Pi^0_1</math> sentence. However, modified versions of Hilbert's program emerged and research has been carried out on related topics. This has led, in particular, to: *Refinement of Gödel's result, particularly [[J. Barkley Rosser]]'s refinement, weakening the above requirement of ω-consistency to simple consistency; *Axiomatisation of the core of Gödel's result in terms of a modal language, [[provability logic]]; *Transfinite iteration of theories, due to [[Alan Turing]] and [[Solomon Feferman]]; *The discovery of [[self-verifying theories]], systems strong enough to talk about themselves, but too weak to carry out the [[diagonal lemma|diagonal argument]] that is the key to Gödel's unprovability argument. In parallel to the rise and fall of Hilbert's program, the foundations of [[structural proof theory]] were being founded. [[Jan Łukasiewicz]] suggested in 1926 that one could improve on [[Hilbert system]]s as a basis for the axiomatic presentation of logic if one allowed the drawing of conclusions from assumptions in the inference rules of the logic. In response to this, [[Stanisław Jaśkowski]] (1929) and [[Gerhard Gentzen]] (1934) independently provided such systems, called calculi of [[natural deduction]], with Gentzen's approach introducing the idea of symmetry between the grounds for asserting propositions, expressed in [[introduction rule]]s, and the consequences of accepting propositions in the [[elimination rule]]s, an idea that has proved very important in proof theory.<ref>{{harvtxt|Prawitz|1965|p=98}}.</ref> Gentzen (1934) further introduced the idea of the [[sequent calculus]], a calculus advanced in a similar spirit that better expressed the duality of the logical connectives,{{sfn|Girard|Taylor|Lafont|2003}} and went on to make fundamental advances in the formalisation of intuitionistic logic, and provide the first [[combinatorial proof]] of the consistency of [[Peano arithmetic]]. Together, the presentation of natural deduction and the sequent calculus introduced the fundamental idea of [[analytic proof]] to proof theory.
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)