Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Propositional calculus
(section)
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
== History == {{main|History of logic}} Although propositional logic had been hinted by earlier philosophers, [[Chrysippus]] is often credited with development of a deductive system for propositional logic as his main achievement in the 3rd century BC<ref name="ms1"/> which was expanded by his successor [[Stoics]]. The logic was focused on [[proposition]]s. This was different from the traditional [[syllogism|syllogistic logic]], which focused on [[Syllogisms#Terms in syllogism|terms]]. However, most of the original writings were lost<ref name="ms2"/> and, at some time between the 3rd and 6th century CE, Stoic logic faded into oblivion, to be resurrected only in the 20th century, in the wake of the (re)-discovery of propositional logic.<ref name="ms3"/> [[Symbolic logic]], which would come to be important to refine propositional logic, was first developed by the 17th/18th-century mathematician [[Gottfried Leibniz]], whose [[calculus ratiocinator]] was, however, unknown to the larger logical community. Consequently, many of the advances achieved by Leibniz were recreated by logicians like [[George Boole]] and [[Augustus De Morgan]], completely independent of Leibniz.<ref name="ms4"/> [[Gottlob Frege|Gottlob Frege's]] [[predicate logic]] builds upon propositional logic, and has been described as combining "the distinctive features of syllogistic logic and propositional logic."<ref name="ms5"/> Consequently, predicate logic ushered in a new era in logic's history; however, advances in propositional logic were still made after Frege, including [[natural deduction]], [[Method of analytic tableaux|truth trees]] and [[truth-table|truth tables]]. Natural deduction was invented by [[Gerhard Gentzen]] and [[Stanisław Jaśkowski]]. Truth trees were invented by [[Evert Willem Beth]].<ref name="ms6"/> The invention of truth tables, however, is of uncertain attribution. Within works by Frege<ref name="Truth in Frege"/> and [[Bertrand Russell]],<ref name="Russell Truth-Tables"/> are ideas influential to the invention of truth tables. The actual tabular structure (being formatted as a table), itself, is generally credited to either [[Ludwig Wittgenstein]] or [[Emil Post]] (or both, independently).<ref name="Truth in Frege" /> Besides Frege and Russell, others credited with having ideas preceding truth tables include Philo, Boole, [[Charles Sanders Peirce]],<ref name="ms7"/> and [[Ernst Schröder (mathematician)|Ernst Schröder]]. Others credited with the tabular structure include [[Jan Łukasiewicz]], [[Alfred North Whitehead]], [[William Stanley Jevons]], [[John Venn]], and [[Clarence Irving Lewis]].<ref name="Russell Truth-Tables" /> Ultimately, some have concluded, like John Shosky, that "It is far from clear that any one person should be given the title of 'inventor' of truth-tables".<ref name="Russell Truth-Tables" />
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)