Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Semiotics
(section)
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
== History and terminology == The importance of signs and signification has been recognized throughout much of the history of [[philosophy]] and [[psychology]]. The term derives {{etymology|grc|''σημειωτικός'' (sēmeiōtikós)|observant of signs}}<ref>Liddell, Henry George, and Robert Scott. 1940. "σημειωτικός." ''[[A Greek-English Lexicon]]''. Revised and augmented by H. S. Jones and R. McKenzie. Oxford: [[Clarendon Press]]. Available via ''[https://www.perseus.tufts.edu/hopper/text?doc=Perseus%3Atext%3A1999.04.0057%3Aentry%3Dshmeiwtiko%2Fs Perseus Digital Library]''.</ref> ({{etymology||''σημεῖον'' (sēmeîon)|a sign, mark, token}}).<ref>[https://www.perseus.tufts.edu/hopper/text?doc=Perseus%3Atext%3A1999.04.0057%3Aentry%3Dshmei%3Don σημεῖον], Henry George Liddell, Robert Scott, ''A Greek-English Lexicon'', on Perseus</ref> For the Greeks, 'signs' ({{Linktext|σημεῖον}} {{Lang|grc-latn|sēmeîon}}) occurred in the world of nature and 'symbols' ({{Linktext|σύμβολον}} {{Lang|grc-latn|sýmbolon}}) in the world of culture. As such, [[Plato]] and [[Aristotle]] explored the relationship between signs and the world.<ref>{{Cite web|url=http://visual-memory.co.uk/daniel/Documents/S4B/sem02.html|title=Semiotics for Beginners: Signs|website=visual-memory.co.uk|access-date=2017-03-26}}</ref> It would not be until [[Augustine of Hippo]]<ref>[[John Deely|Deely, John]]. 2009. ''Augustine & Poinsot: The Protosemiotic Development.'' Scranton: [[University of Scranton Press]]. [provides full details of Augustine's originality on the notion of semiotics.]</ref> that the nature of the sign would be considered within a conventional system. Augustine introduced a thematic proposal for uniting the two under the notion of 'sign' ({{Lang|la|signum}}) as transcending the [[nature–culture divide]] and identifying symbols as no more than a species (or sub-species) of ''{{Lang|la|signum}}''.<ref>Romeo, Luigi. 1977. "The Derivation of 'Semiotics' through the History of the Discipline." ''Semiosis'' 6(2):37–49.</ref> A monograph study on this question was done by Manetti (1987).<ref>Manetti, Giovanni. 1993 [1987]. ''Theories of the Sign in Classical Antiquity'', translated by C. Richardson. Bloomington, IN: [[Indiana University Press]]. [Original: ''Le teorie del segno nell'antichità classica'' (1987)''.'' Milan: [[Bompiani]].]</ref><ref group="lower-alpha">See also [http://permalink.gmane.org/gmane.science.philosophy.peirce/3252 Andrew LaVelle's discussion of Romeo on Peirce]. {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20181001220553/http://permalink.gmane.org/gmane.science.philosophy.peirce/3252|date=2018-10-01}}.</ref> These theories have had a lasting effect in [[Western philosophy]], especially through [[Scholasticism|scholastic]] philosophy.{{cn|date=February 2025}} The general study of signs that began in Latin with Augustine culminated with the 1632 {{Lang|la|Tractatus de Signis}} of [[John Poinsot]] and then began anew in late modernity with the attempt in 1867 by [[Charles Sanders Peirce]] to draw up a "new list of [[Categories (Peirce)|categories]]". More recently [[Umberto Eco]], in his ''Semiotics and the Philosophy of Language'', has argued that semiotic theories are implicit in the work of most, perhaps all, major thinkers.{{cn|date=February 2025}} === John Locke<!--Linked from 'John Locke'--> === [[John Locke]] (1690), himself a man of [[medicine]], was familiar with this "semeiotics" as naming a specialized branch within medical science. In his personal library were two editions of Scapula's 1579 abridgement of [[Henri Estienne|Henricus Stephanus]]' {{Lang|la|Thesaurus Graecae Linguae}}, which listed {{Lang|grc|σημειωτική}} as the name for {{Gloss|diagnostics}},<ref>"Semiotics." ''Oxford English Dictionary'' (1989). ["The branch of medical science relating to the interpretation of symptoms."]</ref> the branch of medicine concerned with interpreting symptoms of disease ("[[symptomatology]]"). Physician and scholar [[Henry Stubbe]] (1670) had transliterated this term of specialized science into English precisely as "''semeiotics''", marking the first use of the term in English:<ref>[[Henry Stubbe|Stubbes, Henry]]. 1670. ''The Plus Ultra reduced to a Non Plus.'' London. p. 75.</ref>{{blockquote|text="...nor is there any thing to be relied upon in Physick, but an exact knowledge of medicinal phisiology (founded on observation, not principles), semeiotics, method of curing, and tried (not excogitated, not commanding) medicines...."}}Locke would use the term ''sem(e)iotike'' in ''[[An Essay Concerning Human Understanding]]'' (book IV, chap. 21),<ref>Encyclopedia Britannica. 2020 [1998]. "[https://www.britannica.com/science/semiotics Semiotics: Study of Signs]." ''[[Encyclopædia Britannica|Encyclopedia Britannica]]''. Accessed 8 April 2020 Web.</ref><ref group="lower-alpha">Locke (1700) uses the Greek word {{sic|"σημιωτική"|expected=ει, not ι|nolink=}} in the [https://books.google.com/books?id=hGeKsjjtu6EC 4th edition] of his ''Essay concerning Human Understanding'' (p. 437). He notably writes both (a) "σημιωτικὴ"<!--non-capitalized first letter and featuring a grave-accented last vowel; see p. 437 (main text)--> and (b) "Σημιωτική"<!--capitalized first letter and featuring an acute-accented last vowel; see p. 437 (margins)-->: when term (a) is followed by any kind of punctuation mark, it takes the form (b). In Chapter XX, titled "Division of the Sciences," which concludes the 1st edition of Locke's ''Essay'' (1689/1690), Locke introduces "σημιωτική" in § 4 as his proposed name synonymous with "''the Doctrine of Signs''" for the development of the future study of the ubiquitous role of signs within human awareness. In the 4th edition of Locke's ''Essay'' (1700), a new Chapter XIX, titled "Of Enthusiasm," is inserted into Book IV. As result, Chapter XX of the 1st edition becomes Chapter XXI for all subsequent editions. It is an important fact that Locke's proposal for the development of semiotics, with three passing exceptions as "asides" in the writings of [[George Berkeley|Berkeley]], [[Leibniz]], and [[Étienne Bonnot de Condillac|Condillac]], "is met with a resounding silence that lasts as long as modernity itself. Even Locke's devoted late modern editor, [[Alexander Campbell Fraser]], dismisses out of hand 'this crude and superficial scheme of Locke'" Deely adds "Locke's modest proposal subversive of the way of ideas, its reception, and its bearing on the resolution of an ancient and a modern controversy in logic." In the Oxford University Press critical edition (1975), prepared and introduced by Peter Harold Nidditch, Nidditch tells us, in his "Foreword," that he presents us with "a complete, critically established, and unmodernized text that aims at being historically faithful to Locke's final intentions";{{Rp|vii}} that "the present text is based on the original fourth edition of the ''Essay'';{{Rp|xxv}} and that "readings in the other early authorized editions are adopted, in appropriate form, where necessary, and recorded otherwise in the textual notes."{{Rp|xxv}} The term "σημιωτική" appears in that 4th edition (1700), the last published (but not the last prepared) within Locke's lifetime, with exactly the spelling and final accent found in the 1st edition. Yet if we turn to (the final) chapter XXI of the Oxford edition (1975, p. 720), we find not "σημιωτικὴ" but rather do we find substituted the "σημειωτικὴ" spelling (and with final accent reversed). '''Note''' that in [[Greek orthography|Modern Greek]] and in [[Pronunciation of Ancient Greek in teaching|some systems for pronouncing classical Greek]], "σημ'''ι'''ωτική" and "σημ'''ει'''ωτική" are pronounced the same.</ref> in which he explains how science may be divided into three parts:<ref name=":12">[[John Locke|Locke, John]]. 1963 [1823]. ''[[An Essay Concerning Human Understanding]].''</ref>{{Rp|174}} {{blockquote|All that can fall within the compass of human understanding, being either, first, the nature of things, as they are in themselves, their relations, and their manner of operation: or, secondly, that which man himself ought to do, as a rational and voluntary agent, for the attainment of any end, especially happiness: or, thirdly, the ways and means whereby the knowledge of both the one and the other of these is attained and communicated; I think science may be divided properly into these three sorts.||title=|source=}} Locke then elaborates on the nature of this third category, naming it {{Lang|grc|Σημειωτική}} ({{Lang|grc-latn|Semeiotike}}), and explaining it as "the doctrine of signs" in the following terms:<ref name=":12" />{{Rp|175}} {{blockquote|Thirdly, the third branch [of sciences] may be termed {{lang|grc|σημειωτικὴ}}, or the doctrine of signs, the most usual whereof being words, it is aptly enough termed also {{lang|grc|Λογικὴ}}, logic; the business whereof is to consider the nature of signs the mind makes use of for the understanding of things, or conveying its knowledge to others.||title=|source=}} [[Juri Lotman]] introduced Eastern Europe to semiotics and adopted Locke's coinage ({{Lang|grc|Σημειωτική}}) as the name to subtitle his founding at the [[University of Tartu]] in Estonia in 1964 of the first semiotics journal, ''[[Sign Systems Studies]]''. === Ferdinand de Saussure === [[Ferdinand de Saussure]] founded his semiotics, which he called [[Ferdinand de Saussure#Language as semiology|semiology]], in the social sciences:<ref>Cited in [[Daniel Chandler|Chandler, Daniel]]. ''Semiotics for Beginners''. "Introduction."</ref> {{blockquote|It is...possible to conceive of a science which studies the role of signs as part of social life. It would form part of social psychology, and hence of general psychology. We shall call it semiology (from the Greek ''semeîon'', 'sign'). It would investigate the nature of signs and the laws governing them. Since it does not yet exist, one cannot say for certain that it will exist. But it has a right to exist, a place ready for it in advance. Linguistics is only one branch of this general science. The laws which semiology will discover will be laws applicable in linguistics, and linguistics will thus be assigned to a clearly defined place in the field of human knowledge. ||title=|source=}} [[Thomas Sebeok]]<ref group="lower-alpha">The whole anthology, ''Frontiers in Semiotics'', was devoted to the documentation of this ''pars pro toto'' move of Sebeok.</ref> would assimilate ''semiology'' to ''semiotics'' as a part to a whole, and was involved in choosing the name ''[[Semiotica]]'' for the first international journal devoted to the study of signs. Saussurean semiotics have exercised a great deal of influence on the schools of structuralism and post-structuralism. [[Jacques Derrida]], for example, takes as his object the Saussurean relationship of signifier and signified, asserting that signifier and signified are not fixed, coining the expression {{Lang|fr|différance}}, relating to the endless deferral of meaning, and to the absence of a "transcendent signified". === Charles Sanders Peirce === In the nineteenth century, [[Charles Sanders Peirce]] defined what he termed "semiotic" (which he would sometimes spell as "semeiotic") as the "quasi-necessary, or formal doctrine of signs," which abstracts "what must be the characters of all signs used by...an intelligence capable of learning by experience,"<ref>[[Charles Sanders Peirce|Peirce, Charles Sanders]]. ''Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce'', vol. 2: para. 227.</ref> and which is philosophical logic pursued in terms of signs and sign processes.<ref>[[Charles Sanders Peirce|Peirce, Charles Sanders.]] 1998 [1902]. "[http://www.cspeirce.com/menu/library/bycsp/l75/l75.htm Logic, Regarded As Semeiotic]," [manuscript L75] ''Arisbe: The Peirce Gateway'', edited by J. Ransdell.</ref><ref>[[Charles Sanders Peirce|Peirce, Charles Sanders.]] 1998 [1902]. "[http://www.cspeirce.com/menu/library/bycsp/l75/ver1/l75v1-05.htm#m12 On the Definition of Logic]." [memoir 12]. ''Arisbe: The Peirce Gateway'', edited by J. Ransdell.</ref> Peirce's perspective is considered as philosophical logic studied in terms of signs that are not always linguistic or artificial, and sign processes, modes of inference, and the inquiry process in general. The Peircean semiotic addresses not only the external communication mechanism, as per Saussure, but the internal representation machine, investigating sign processes, and modes of inference, as well as the whole inquiry process in general.{{cn|date=February 2025}} Peircean semiotic is triadic, including sign, object, interpretant, as opposed to the dyadic [[Ferdinand de Saussure|Saussurian]] tradition (signifier, signified). Peircean semiotics further subdivides each of the three triadic elements into three sub-types, positing the existence of signs that are symbols; semblances ("icons"); and "indices," i.e., signs that are such through a factual connection to their objects.<ref>{{Citation |last=Atkin |first=Albert |title=Peirce's Theory of Signs |date=2023 |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2023/entries/peirce-semiotics/ |encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |editor-last=Zalta |editor-first=Edward N. |access-date=2023-03-21 |edition=Spring 2023 |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |editor2-last=Nodelman |editor2-first=Uri}}</ref> Peircean scholar and editor Max H. Fisch (1978)<ref group="lower-alpha">Max Fisch has compiled Peirce-related bibliographical supplements in 1952, 1964, 1966, 1974; was consulting editor on the 1977 microfilm of Peirce's published works and on the ''Comprehensive Bibliography'' associated with it; was among the main editors of the first five volumes of ''Writings of Charles S. Peirce'' (1981–1993); and wrote a number of published articles on Peirce, many collected in 1986 in ''Peirce, Semeiotic, and Pragmatism.'' See also [[Charles Sanders Peirce bibliography]].</ref> would claim that "semeiotic" was Peirce's own preferred rendering of Locke's σημιωτική.<ref>Fisch, Max H. (1978), "Peirce's General Theory of Signs" in ''Sight, Sound, and Sense'', ed. T. A. Sebeok. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, pp. 31–70.</ref> [[Charles W. Morris]] followed Peirce in using the term "semiotic" and in extending the discipline beyond human communication to animal learning and use of signals. While the Saussurean semiotic is dyadic (sign/syntax, signal/semantics), the Peircean semiotic is triadic (sign, object, interpretant), being conceived as philosophical logic studied in terms of signs that are not always linguistic or artificial. ==== Peirce's list of categories ==== Peirce would aim to base his new list directly upon experience precisely as constituted by action of signs, in contrast with the list of Aristotle's categories which aimed to articulate within experience the dimension of being that is independent of experience and knowable as such, through human understanding.{{cn|date=February 2025}} The estimative powers of animals interpret the environment as sensed to form a "meaningful world" of objects, but the objects of this world (or ''[[Umwelt]]'', in [[Jakob von Uexküll]]'s term)<ref>2001. "''Umwelt''". ''[[Semiotica]]'' 134(1). Pp. 125–135. [special issue on "Jakob von Uexküll: A paradigm for biology and semiotics," guest-edited by [[Kalevi Kull|K. Kull]].]</ref> consist exclusively of objects related to the animal as desirable (+), undesirable (–), or "safe to ignore" (0). In contrast to this, human understanding adds to the animal ''Umwelt'' a relation of self-identity within objects which transforms objects experienced into 'things' as well as +, –, 0 objects.<ref name=":2">[[Martin Heidegger|Heidegger, Martin.]] 1962 [1927]. ''[[Being and Time]]'', translated by J. Macquarrie and E. Robinson. New York: [[Harper (publisher)|Harper & Row]]. p. 487.</ref><ref group="lower-alpha">"The distinction between the being of existing ''Dasein'' and the Being of entities, such as Reality, which do not have the character of ''Dasein''...is nothing with which philosophy may tranquilize itself. It has long been known that ancient ontology works with 'Thing-concepts' and that there is a danger of 'reifying consciousness'. But what does this 'reifying' signify? Where does it arise? Why does Being get 'conceived' 'proximally' in terms of the present-at-hand and not in terms of the ready-to-hand, which indeed lies ''closer'' to us? Why does reifying always keep coming back to exercise its dominion? This is the question that the ''Umwelt/Lebenswelt'' distinction as here drawn answers to." [[Martin Heidegger]] 1962/1927:486</ref> Thus, the generically animal objective world as ''Umwelt'', becomes a species-specifically human objective world or {{Lang|de|Lebenswelt}} ({{Gloss|life-world}}), wherein linguistic communication, rooted in the biologically underdetermined {{Lang|de|Innenwelt}} ({{Gloss|inner-world}}) of humans, makes possible the further dimension of cultural organization within the otherwise merely social organization of non-human animals whose powers of observation may deal only with directly sensible instances of objectivity.{{cn|date=February 2025}} This further point, that human culture depends upon language understood first of all not as communication, but as the biologically underdetermined aspect or feature of the human animal's ''{{Lang|de|Innenwelt}}'', was originally clearly identified by [[Thomas Sebeok|Thomas A. Sebeok]].<ref>[[Thomas Sebeok|Sebeok, Thomas A.]] 1986. "Communication, Language, and Speech. Evolutionary Considerations." Pp. 10–16 in ''I Think I Am A Verb. More Contributions to the Doctrine of Signs''. New York: [[Plenum Press]]. Published lecture. Original lecture title "The Evolution of Communication and the Origin of Language," in ''International Summer Institute for Semiotic and Structural Studies'' ''Colloquium on 'Phylogeny and Ontogeny of Communication Systems''' (June 1–3, 1984).</ref><ref>[[Thomas Sebeok|Sebeok, Thomas A]]. 2012. "[http://www.augustoponzio.com/files/12._Deely.pdf Afterword]." Pp. 365–83 in ''Semiotic Prologues'', edited by [[John Deely|J. Deely]] and [[Marcel Danesi|M. Danesi]]. Ottawa: Legas.</ref> Sebeok also played the central role in bringing Peirce's work to the center of the semiotic stage in the twentieth century,<ref group="lower-alpha">Detailed demonstration of Sebeok's role of the global emergence of semiotics is recorded in at least three recent volumes: # ''Semiotics Seen Synchronically. The View from 2010'' (Ottawa: Legas, 2010). # ''Semiotics Continues To Astonish. Thomas A. Sebeok and the Doctrine of Signs'' (Berlin: Mouton De Gruyter, 2011)—a 526-page assemblage of essays, vignettes, letters, pictures attesting to the depth and extent of Sebeok's promotion of semiotic understanding around the world, including his involvement with Juri Lotman and the Tartu University graduate program in semiotics (currently directed by P. Torop, M. Lotman and K. Kull). # Sebeok's ''Semiotic Prologues'' (Ottawa: Legas, 2012)—a volume which gathers together in Part I all the "prologues" (i.e., introductions, prefaces, forewords, etc.) that Sebeok wrote for other peoples' books, then in Part 2 all the "prologues" that other people wrote for Sebeok.</ref> first with his expansion of the human use of signs (''anthroposemiosis'') to include also the generically animal sign-usage (''zoösemiosis''),<ref group="lower-alpha">See [[Thomas Sebeok|Sebeok, Thomas A]]. "Communication in Animals and Men." A review article that covers three books: Martin Lindauer, ''Communication among Social Bees'' (Harvard Books in Biology, No. 2; Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1961, pp. ix + 143); Winthrop N. Kellogg, Porpoises and Sonar (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1961, pp. xiv + 177); and John C. Lilly, ''Man and Dolphin'' (Garden City, New York: Doubleday), in ''Language'' 39 (1963), 448–466.</ref> then with his further expansion of semiosis to include the vegetative world (''phytosemiosis''). Such would initially be based on the work of [[Martin Krampen]],<ref>[[Martin Krampen|Krampen, Martin]]. 1981. "Phytosemiotics." ''[[Semiotica]]'' 36(3):187–209.</ref> but takes advantage of Peirce's point that an interpretant, as the third item within a sign relation, "need not be mental".<ref>[[Charles Sanders Peirce|Peirce, Charles Sanders]]. 1934 [1907] "A Survey of Pragmaticism." P. 473. in ''The Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce'' 5, edited by [[Charles Hartshorne|C. Hartshorne]] and P. Weiss. Cambridge, MA: [[Harvard University Press]]. [originally titled "Excerpt from "Pragmatism (Editor [3])"]</ref><ref>[[Charles Sanders Peirce|Peirce, Charles Sanders]]. 1977 [1908]. "letter to Lady Welby 23 December 1908" [letter]. Pp. 73–86 in ''Semiotic and Significs: The Correspondence between C. S. Peirce and Victoria Lady Welby'', edited by C. S. Hardwick and J. Cook. Bloomington, IN: [[Indiana University Press]].</ref><ref>[[Charles Sanders Peirce|Peirce, Charles Sanders]]. 2009. "Semiosis: The Subject Matter of Semiotic Inquiry." Pp. 26–50 in ''Basics of Semiotics'' (5th ed.), edited by [[John Deely|J. Deely]]. Tartu, Estonia: [[Tartu University Press]]. See especially pp. 31,38– 41.</ref> Peirce distinguished between the interpretant and the interpreter. The interpretant is the internal, mental representation that mediates between the object and its sign. The interpreter is the human who is creating the interpretant.<ref>{{Cite web |url=http://courses.logos.it/EN/2_18.html|title=LOGOS – Multilingual Translation Portal |website=courses.logos.it |access-date=2017-03-26}}</ref> Peirce's "interpretant" notion opened the way to understanding an action of signs beyond the realm of animal life (study of phytosemiosis + zoösemiosis + anthroposemiosis = ''biosemiotics''), which was his first advance beyond Latin Age semiotics.<ref group="lower-alpha">For a summary of Peirce's contributions to semiotics, see Liszka (1996) or Atkin (2006).</ref> Other early theorists in the field of semiotics include [[Charles W. Morris]].<ref>1971, orig. 1938, ''Writings on the general theory of signs'', Mouton, The Hague, The Netherlands</ref> Writing in 1951, [[Jozef Maria Bochenski]] surveyed the field in this way: "Closely related to mathematical logic is the so-called semiotics (Charles Morris) which is now commonly employed by mathematical logicians. Semiotics is the theory of symbols and falls in three parts; # logical syntax, the theory of the mutual relations of symbols, # logical semantics, the theory of the relations between the symbol and what the symbol stands for, and # logical pragmatics, the relations between symbols, their meanings and the users of the symbols."<ref>Jozef Maria Bochenski (1956) ''Contemporary European Philosophy'', trans. Donald Nichols and Karl Ashenbrenner from 1951 edition, Berkeley, CA: University of California, Section 25, "Mathematical Logic," Subsection F, "Semiotics," p. 259.</ref> [[Max Black]] argued that the work of [[Bertrand Russell]] was seminal in the field.<ref>Black, Max. 1944. ''The Philosophy of Bertrand Russell'' 5. [[Library of Living Philosophers]].</ref>
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)