Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Unintended consequences
(section)
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
==History== {{original research section|date=September 2024}} ===John Locke=== The idea of ''unintended consequences'' dates back at least to [[John Locke]] who discussed the unintended consequences of [[interest rate]] [[regulation]] in his letter to Sir John Somers, Member of Parliament.<ref>John Locke, [http://oll.libertyfund.org/titles/763#lf0128-04_head_002''The Works of John Locke in Nine Volumes''], (London: Rivington, 1824 12th ed.). Vol. 4.</ref> ===Adam Smith=== The idea was also discussed by [[Adam Smith]], the [[Scottish Enlightenment]], and [[consequentialism]] (judging by results).<ref>{{cite web|last=Smith|first=Adam|title=The Theory of Moral Sentiments|page=93|url=http://metalibri.wikidot.com/title:theory-of-moral-sentiments:smith-a}}</ref> The [[Invisible hand|invisible hand theorem]] is an example of the unintended consequences of agents acting in their self-interest. As [[Andrew Stewart Skinner|Andrew S. Skinner]] puts it:<blockquote>"The individual undertaker ([[Entrepreneurship|entrepreneur]]), seeking the most efficient allocation of resources, contributes to overall [[economic efficiency]]; the merchant's reaction to price signals helps to ensure that the allocation of resources accurately reflects the structure of consumer preferences; and the drive to better our condition contributes to [[economic growth]]."<ref>{{Cite book |last=Stewart Skinner |first=Andrew |title=Handbook of the history of economic thought: insights on the founders of modern economics |date=2012 |publisher=Springer |editor=Jürgen G. Backhaus |isbn=978-1-4419-8336-7 |location=New York |page=171 |oclc=761868679}}</ref></blockquote> ===Marx and Engels=== Influenced by 19th century [[positivism]]<ref>{{harvnb|Saint-Upéry|2015|p= 146}}: Por supuesto, la raíz de esta posible mutación dogmática se puede identificar en la concepción de la «ciencia» de Marx, mezcla de Wissenschaft especulativa hegeliana y evolucionismo positivista típico del siglo XIX. [Of course, the root of this possible dogmatic mutation can be identified on Marx's conception of "science", a mix of speculative hegelian Wissenschaft and positivist evolutionism typical of the 19 century.]</ref> and [[Charles Darwin]]'s [[Theory of Evolution|evolution]], for both Friedrich Engels and Karl Marx, the idea of uncertainty and chance in social dynamics (and thus unintended consequences beyond results of perfectly defined laws) was only apparent, (if not rejected) since social actions were directed and produced by deliberate human intention.<ref>{{harvnb|Saint-Upéry|2015|p= 147}}: Es bien conocida la admiración de Marx y Engels por el autor de El origen de las especies y su ambición más o menos explícita de hacer para la evolución social lo que el científico británico había hecho para la evolución natural. Sin embargo, la interpretación de la selección natural por Marx era parcialmente defectiva. Reprochaba a Darwin el rol excesivo otorgado al azar en su esquema de evolución y defendía a veces en modo más bien implícito una especie de lamarckismo sociológico en el que la supuesta función político-ideológica o económica crea inevitablemente el órgano social adecuado en cada etapa del desarrollo de la humanidad. [Marx and Engels admiration for the author of On the Origin of Species and their more or less explicit ambition to do for social evolution what the british scientist did for natural evolution is well known. However, Marx's interpretation of natural selection was partially defective. He reproached Darwin for the excessive role given to chance in his scheme of evolution and defended -sometimes in a more implicit manner- a kind of sociological Lamarckism in which the supposed political-ideological or economic function inevitably creates the adequate social organ on each stage of human [historical] development.]</ref><ref>{{harvnb|Engels|1946| }}: In the history of society, on the contrary, the actors are all endowed with consciousness, are men acting with deliberation or passion, working towards definite goals; nothing happens without a conscious purpose, without an intended aim.</ref> While discerning between the forces that generate changes in nature and those that generate changes in history in his discussion of [[Ludwig Feuerbach]], [[Friedrich Engels]] touched on the idea of (apparent) unintended consequences: :{{Blockquote|In nature [...] there are only blind, unconscious agencies acting upon one another, [...] In the history of society, on the contrary, the actors are all endowed with consciousness, are men acting with deliberation or passion, working towards definite goals; nothing happens without a conscious purpose, without an intended aim. [...] For here, also, on the whole, in spite of the consciously desired aims of all individuals, accident apparently reigns on the surface. That which is willed happens but rarely; in the majority of instances the numerous desired ends cross and conflict with one another, or these ends themselves are from the outset incapable of realization, or the means of attaining them are insufficient. Thus the conflicts of innumerable individual wills and individual actions in the domain of history produce a state of affairs entirely analogous to [...] the realm of unconscious nature. The ends of the actions are intended, but the results which actually follow from these actions are not intended; or when they do seem to correspond to the end intended, they ultimately have consequences quite other than those intended. Historical events thus appear on the whole to be likewise governed by chance. But where on the surface accident holds sway, there actually it is always governed by inner, hidden laws, and it is only a matter of discovering these laws.|[[Ludwig Feuerbach and the End of Classical German Philosophy]] (Ludwig Feuerbach und der Ausgang der klassischen deutschen Philosophie), 1886.<ref>{{harvnb|Engels|1946| }}:</ref>|col2=|col3=}} For his part, for [[Karl Marx]] what can be understood as unintended consequences are actually consequences that should be expected but are obtained unconsciously. These consequences (that no one consciously sought) would be (in the same way as it is for Engels<ref>{{harvnb|Vernon|1979|p= 69}}: Engels traces the occurrence of "what no one has willed" exclusively to the fact of conflict among actors</ref><ref name="Vernon">{{harvnb|Vernon|1979|p= 63}}: But the unintended consequences arising from diversity of ends, as we have noted already, are sometimes seen as emphatically good; they may be seen (as in Hayek) in the light of immanent spontaneous cooperation, no less than (as in Engels) in the light of destructive contradictions.</ref>) product of conflicts that confront actions from countless individuals. The deviation between the original intended goal and the product derived from conflicts would be a marxist equivalent to «unintended consequences.»<ref>{{harvnb|Vernon|1979|p= 58}}: "History is made in such a way that the final result always arises from conflicts between many individual wills... Thus there are innumerable intersecting forces, an infinite series of parallelograms of forces, which give rise to one resultant-the historical event... For what each individual wills is obstructed by everyone else, and what emerges is something that no one willed. Thus past history proceeds in the manner of a natural process... "</ref> This social conflicts would happen as a result of a competitive society, and also lead society to sabotage itself and prevent historical progress.<ref>{{harvnb|Vernon|1979|p= 58}}: [For Marx and Engels] Unintended consequences are a feature not of "history" in general but of "past history", an expression of the inherently self-defeating tendencies of a competitive and inegalitarian society.</ref> Thus, historical progress (in Marxist terms) should eliminate these conflicts and make unintended consequences predictable.<ref>{{harvnb|Vernon|1979|p= 58}}: If this is so, then we may imagine a future order in which the rational coordination of efforts brings about a course of events which will have been consciously intended.</ref> ===Austrian School=== Unintended consequences are a common topic of study and commentary for the [[Austrian school of economics]] given its emphasis on [[methodological individualism]]. This is to such an extent that unexpected consequences can be considered as a distinctive part of Austrian tenets.<ref>{{harvnb|O'Driscoll Jr.|2004|p= 272}}: As Caldwell observes, "Menger's Principle of Economics is the founding document of the Austrian School of Economics, [...]" In it, Menger developed what became "fundamental Austrian tenets: the connection between time and error; the causal-genetic or compositive methodological approach; and the notion of unintended consequences".</ref> ====Carl Menger==== In "[[Principles of Economics (Menger book)|Principles of Economics]]", Austrian school founder [[Carl Menger]] (1840 - 1921) noted that the relationships that occur in the economy are so intricate that a change in the condition of a single [[Goods|good]] can have ramifications beyond that good. Menger wrote: :{{Blockquote|If it is established that the existence of human needs capable of satisfaction is a prerequisite of goods-character [...] This principle is valid whether the goods can be placed in ''direct causal'' connection with the satisfaction of human needs, or derive their goods-character from a more or less indirect causal connection with the satisfaction of human needs. [...]<br/>Thus [[quinine]] would cease to be a good if the [[Malaria|diseases it serves to cure]] should disappear, since the only need with the satisfaction of which it is causally connected would no longer exist. But the disappearance of the usefulness of quinine would have the further consequence that a large part of the corresponding goods of higher order would also be deprived of their goods-character. The inhabitants of quinine-producing countries, who currently earn their livings by cutting and peeling [[cinchona]] trees, would suddenly find that not only their stocks of cinchona bark, but also, in consequence, their cinchona trees, the tools and appliances applicable only to the production of quinine, and above all the specialized labor services, by means of which they previously earned their livings, would at once lose their goods-character, since all these things would, under the changed circumstances, no longer have any causal relationship with the satisfaction of human needs.|Principles of Economics (Grundsätze der Volkswirtschaftslehre), 1871.<ref>{{harvnb|Menger|2007|pp= 64–65}}:</ref>|col2=|col3=}} ====Friedrich Hayek and Catallactics==== Economist and philosopher [[Friedrich Hayek]] (1899 – 1992) is another key figure in the Austrian School of Economics who is notable for his comments on unintended consequences.<ref>{{harvnb|O'Driscoll Jr.|2004|p= 279}}: [Hayek's] enduring contributions to the study of the unintended consequences of human action are among his most famous achievements. By elaborating that concept, Hayek developed a theory of institutions that spans economics and politics. A full appreciation of Hayek's ideas on unintended consequences would require an essay in its.</ref> In "[[The Use of Knowledge in Society]]" (1945) Hayek argues that a centrally [[planned economy]] cannot reach the level of efficiency of the [[free market]] economy because the necessary (and pertinent) information for decision-making is not concentrated but dispersed among a vast number of agents.<ref>{{harvnb|Hayek|1996|}}:The peculiar character of the problem of a rational economic order is determined precisely by the fact that the knowledge of the circumstances of which we must make use never exists in concentrated or integrated form but solely as the dispersed bits of incomplete and frequently contradictory knowledge which all the separate individuals possess. [...] It is rather a problem of how to secure the best use of resources known to any of the members of society, for ends whose relative importance only these individuals know. Or, to put it briefly, it is a problem of the utilization of knowledge which is not given to anyone in its totality.</ref> Then, for Hayek, the price system in the free market allows the members of a society to anonymously coordinate for the most efficient use of resources, for example, in a situation of scarcity of a raw material, the price increase would coordinate the actions of an uncountable amount of individuals "in the right direction".<ref>{{harvnb|Hayek|1996|}}: The marvel is that in a case like that of a scarcity of one raw material, without an order being issued, without more than perhaps a handful of people knowing the cause, tens of thousands of people whose identity could not be ascertained by months of investigation, are made to use the material or its products more sparingly; i.e., they move in the right direction.</ref> The development of this system of interactions would allow the progress of society,<ref>{{harvnb|Hayek|1996|}}:The price system is just one of those formations which man has learned to use (though he is still very far from having learned to make the best use of it) after he had stumbled upon it without understanding it. Through it not only a division of labor but also a coordinated utilization of resources based on an equally divided knowledge has become possible. [...] man has been able to develop that division of labor on which our civilization is based because he happened to stumble upon a method which made it possible.</ref> and individuals would carry it out without knowing all its implications, given the dispersion (or lack of concentration) of information.<ref>{{harvnb|Hayek|1996|}}:As Alfred Whitehead has said in another connection, "It is a profoundly erroneous truism, [...] that we should cultivate the habit of thinking what we are doing. The precise opposite is the case. Civilization advances by extending the number of important operations which we can perform without thinking about them." This is of profound significance in the social field. We make constant use of formulas, symbols, and rules whose meaning we do not understand and through the use of which we avail ourselves of the assistance of knowledge which individually we do not possess. We have developed these practices and institutions by building upon habits and institutions which have proved successful in their own sphere and which have in turn become the foundation of the civilization we have built up.</ref> The implication of this is that the social order (which derives from social progress, which in turn derives from the economy),<ref>{{harvnb|Vernon|1979|p= 64}}: It turns out to be more difficult than may appear at first sight to define what it is that Hayek regards as the "order". Very frequently he refers to it as something "brought about" by multiple exchanges; it is something that "the market system leads to".</ref> would be result of a spontaneous cooperation and also an unintended consequence,<ref name=Vernon/> being born from a process of which no individual or group had all the information available or could know all possible outcomes. In the Austrian school, this process of social adjustment that generates a social order in an unintendedly way is known as [[catallactics]].<ref>{{harvnb|Vernon|1979|pp= 63–64}}: No word seems quite right as a label for this category of unintended consequences [...] "Catallaxy" is the term which Hayek offers in place of "economy": the latter word, he argues, applies more properly to an organisation such as a business enterprise, and in applying it to the order which such enterprises compose we may be led to see it as a kind of large organisation, which it is not. It is an order spontaneously brought about by multiple transactions or exchanges (katallatein: "to exchange") among organisations. It is not a willed or designed or contrived thing, like an organisational hierarchy, but the unintended outcome of many independent decision.</ref> For Hayek and the Austrian School, the number of individuals involved in the process of creating a social order defines the type of unintended consequence:<ref>{{harvnb|Vernon|1979|p= 64}}: whereas a spontaneous order rests upon decisions made locally by many actors whose aggregate knowledge is much greater than any single actor could have. Moreover, Hayek (unlike Popper) directs his objections not only against attempts to "organise" in a total or "utopian" way but also against more modest "interferences" with the order, which he alleges, always disrupt it. The role of legislation is only to provide a context of essentially general or abstract rules, rules not directed at particular ends nor imposed upon particular persons, which enable men to conduct their transactions in security. It follows necessarily that the general outcomes produced by the order are unintended. For it is no one's business to intend them</ref> # If the process involves interactions and decision making of as many individuals (members of a society) as possible (thus gathering the greatest amount of knowledge dispersed among them), this process of "catallaxy" will lead to unexpected benefits (a social order and progress) # On the other hand, attempts by individuals or limited groups (who lack all the necessary information) to achieve a new or better order, will end in unexpected drawbacks. ===Robert K. Merton=== Sociologist [[Robert K. Merton]] popularised this concept in the twentieth century.<ref name="nytimes.com"/><ref>{{cite web|title=Renowned Columbia Sociologist and National Medal of Science Winner Robert K. Merton Dies at 92 |url=http://www.columbia.edu/cu/news/03/02/robertKMerton.html|publisher=Columbia News}}</ref><ref>[http://www.asanet.org/footnotes/mar03/indextwo.html Robert K. Merton Remembered] Footnotes, American Sociological Association</ref><ref name="Merton"/> In "The Unanticipated Consequences of Purposive Social Action" (1936), Merton tried to apply a systematic analysis to the problem of unintended consequences of deliberate acts intended to cause [[social change]]. He emphasized that his term ''purposive action'', "[was exclusively] concerned with 'conduct' as distinct from 'behavior.' That is, with action that involves motives and consequently a choice between various alternatives".<ref name="Merton">{{cite journal|last=Merton|first=Robert K.|title=The Unanticipated Consequences of Purposive Social Action|journal=[[American Sociological Review]]|volume=1|issue=6|pages=894–904|url=http://www.d.umn.edu/cla/faculty/jhamlin/4111/2111-home/CD/TheoryClass/Readings/MertonSocialAction.pdf |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20130429205921/http://www.d.umn.edu/cla/faculty/jhamlin/4111/2111-home/CD/TheoryClass/Readings/MertonSocialAction.pdf |archive-date=2013-04-29 |url-status=live|access-date=2008-05-30|doi=10.2307/2084615|jstor=2084615|year=1936}}</ref> Merton's usage included deviations from what [[Max Weber]] defined as rational social action: instrumentally rational and value rational.<ref>{{cite book|last=Weber|first=Max|title=Economy and Society |url=https://archive.org/details/economysociety00webe|url-access=registration|publisher=University of California Press|date=1978|pages=[https://archive.org/details/economysociety00webe/page/24 24–25]|isbn=978-0-520-02824-1}}</ref> Merton also stated that "no blanket statement categorically affirming or denying the practical feasibility of ''all'' social planning is warranted."<ref name="Merton"/> ===Everyday usage=== More recently, the ''law of unintended consequences'' has come to be used as an adage or idiomatic warning that an intervention in a [[complex system]] tends to create unanticipated and often undesirable outcomes.<ref name="Norton ">{{cite encyclopedia |last=Norton |first=Rob |editor=David R. Henderson |editor-link=David R. Henderson |encyclopedia=[[Concise Encyclopedia of Economics]] |title=Unintended Consequences |url=http://www.econlib.org/library/Enc/UnintendedConsequences.html |year=2008 |edition= 2nd |publisher=[[Library of Economics and Liberty]] |location=Indianapolis |isbn=978-0-86597-665-8 |oclc=237794267}}</ref><ref>{{cite journal|url=http://heinonline.org/HOL/LandingPage?collection=journals&handle=hein.journals/mislj71&div=24&id=&page= |title= The Law of Unintended Consequences in Asbestos Litigation: How Efforts to Streamline the Litigation Have Fueled More Claims|journal=Mississippi Law Journal |volume=71 |page=531 |publisher=HeinOnline |access-date=2010-05-07|last1=Schwartz |first1=Victor E. |last2=Tedesco |first2=Rochelle M. }}</ref><ref>{{cite journal|url=http://heinonline.org/HOL/LandingPage?collection=journals&handle=hein.journals/flsulr28&div=36&id=&page= |title=28 Florida State University Law Review 2000–2001 Mandatory Minimum Sentences: Exemplifying the Law of Unintended Consequences Comment |journal=Florida State University Law Review |volume=28 |page=935 |publisher=Heinonline.org |date=1993-06-18 |access-date=2012-11-21|last1=Mascharka |first1=Christopher }}</ref><ref>{{cite journal|url=http://heinonline.org/HOL/LandingPage?collection=journals&handle=hein.journals/antil65&div=47&id=&page= |title= The Effect of Twenty Years of Hart-Scott-Rodino on Merger Practice: A Case Study in the Law of Unintended Consequences Applied to Antitrust Legislation|journal=Antitrust Law Journal |volume=65 |page=865 |publisher=HeinOnline |access-date=2010-05-07|last1=Sims |first1=Joe |last2=Herman |first2=Deborah P. }}</ref> Akin to [[Murphy's law]], it is commonly used as a wry or humorous warning against the [[hubris]]tic belief that humans can fully control the world around them, not to presuppose a belief in predestination or a lack or a disbelief in that of free will.
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)