Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Utility
(section)
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
== Utility function == Consider a set of alternatives among which a person has a preference ordering. A '''utility function''' represents that ordering if it is possible to assign a [[real number]] to each alternative in such a manner that ''alternative a'' is assigned a number greater than ''alternative b'' if and only if the individual prefers ''alternative a'' to ''alternative b''. In this situation, someone who selects the most preferred alternative must also choose one that maximizes the associated utility function. Suppose James has utility function <math>U = \sqrt{xy}</math> such that <math>x</math> is the number of apples and <math>y</math> is the number of chocolates. Alternative A has <math>x = 9</math> apples and <math>y = 16</math> chocolates; alternative B has <math>x = 13</math> apples and <math>y = 13</math> chocolates. Putting the values <math>x, y</math> into the utility function yields <math>\sqrt{9 \times 16} = 12</math> for alternative A and <math>\sqrt{13 \times 13} = 13</math> for B, so James prefers alternative B. In general economic terms, a utility function ranks preferences concerning a set of goods and services. [[Gérard Debreu]] derived the conditions required for a preference ordering to be representable by a utility function.<ref>{{citation|last=Debreu|first=Gérard|title=Decision processes|pages=159–167|year=1954|postscript=.|editor-last1=Thrall|editor-first1=Robert M.|contribution=Representation of a preference ordering by a numerical function|location=New York|publisher=Wiley|oclc=639321|editor-last2=Coombs|editor-first2=Clyde H.|editor-last3=Raiffa|editor-first3=Howard|editor-link2=Clyde H. Coombs|editor-link3=Howard Raiffa}}</ref> For a finite set of alternatives, these require only that the preference ordering is complete (so the individual can determine which of any two alternatives is preferred or that they are indifferent), and that the preference order is [[Transitive relation|transitive]]. Suppose the set of alternatives is not finite (for example, even if the number of goods is finite, the quantity chosen can be any real number on an interval). In that case, a continuous utility function exists representing a consumer's preferences if and only if the consumer's preferences are complete, transitive, and continuous.<ref>{{citation|last1=Jehle|first1=Geoffrey|last2=Reny|first2=Philipp|title=Advanced Microeconomic Theory|pages=13–16|year=2011|postscript=.|publisher=Prentice Hall, Financial Times|isbn=978-0-273-73191-7}}</ref>
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)