Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Well-ordering principle
(section)
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
==Properties== Depending on the framework in which the natural numbers are introduced, this (second-order) property of the set of natural numbers is either an [[axiom]] or a provable theorem. For example: * In [[Peano arithmetic]], [[second-order arithmetic]] and related systems, and indeed in most (not necessarily formal) mathematical treatments of the well-ordering principle, the principle is derived from the principle of [[mathematical induction]], which is itself taken as basic. * Considering the natural numbers as a subset of the real numbers, and assuming that we know already that the real numbers are complete (again, either as an axiom or a theorem about the [[real number]] system), i.e., every bounded (from below) set has an infimum, then also every set <math>A</math> of natural numbers has an infimum, say <math>a^*</math>. We can now find an integer <math>n^*</math> such that <math>a^*</math> lies in the half-open interval <math>(n^*-1,n^*]</math>, and can then show that we must have <math>a^* = n^*</math>, and <math>n^*</math> in ''<math>A</math>''. * In [[axiomatic set theory]], the natural numbers are defined as the smallest [[Inductive set (axiom of infinity)|inductive set]] (i.e., set containing 0 and closed under the successor operation). One can (even without invoking the [[axiom of regularity|regularity axiom]]) show that the set of all natural numbers <math>n</math> such that "<math>\{0,\ldots,n\}</math> is well-ordered" is inductive, and must therefore contain all natural numbers; from this property one can conclude that the set of all natural numbers is also well-ordered. In the second sense, this phrase is used when that proposition is relied on for the purpose of justifying proofs that take the following form: to prove that every natural number belongs to a specified set <math>S</math>, assume the contrary, which implies that the set of counterexamples is non-empty and thus contains a smallest [[counterexample]]. Then show that for any counterexample there is a still smaller counterexample, producing a contradiction. This mode of argument is the [[contrapositive]] of proof by [[complete induction]]. It is known light-heartedly as the "[[minimal criminal]]" method<ref>{{cite book | last1 = Lovász | first1 = L. | author1-link = László Lovász | last2 = Pelikán | first2 = J. | last3 = Vesztergombi | first3 = K. | author3-link = Katalin Vesztergombi | doi = 10.1007/b97469 | isbn = 0-387-95584-4 | mr = 1952453 | pages = 90–91 | publisher = Springer-Verlag | location = New York | series = Undergraduate Texts in Mathematics | title = Discrete Mathematics: Elementary and Beyond | url = https://books.google.com/books?id=Tn0pBAAAQBAJ&pg=PA90 | year = 2003}}</ref> and is similar in its nature to [[Fermat|Fermat's]] method of "[[infinite descent]]". [[Garrett Birkhoff]] and [[Saunders Mac Lane]] wrote in ''A Survey of Modern Algebra'' that this property, like the [[least upper bound axiom]] for real numbers, is non-algebraic; i.e., it cannot be deduced from the algebraic properties of the integers (which form an ordered [[integral domain]]).
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)