Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Naturalistic fallacy
(section)
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
===Non-synonymous properties=== In 1939, [[William Frankena]]<ref name="Frankena 1939">{{cite journal |title=The Naturalistic Fallacy |first=W. K. |last=Frankena |journal=Mind |volume=48 |number=192 |date=October 1939 |pages=464β477 |publisher=Oxford University Press |doi=10.1093/mind/XLVIII.192.464 |jstor=2250706}}</ref> critiqued [[G. E. Moore]]'s conception of the naturalistic fallacy. Frankena stated that, in arguing that ''good'' cannot be defined by natural properties, Moore was trying to avoid a broader confusion caused by attempting to define a term using non-synonymous properties.<ref name="IEP Moore">{{cite encyclopedia |title=Moore, George Edward |url=http://www.iep.utm.edu/moore/ |encyclopedia=Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |accessdate=March 31, 2011 |last=Preston |first=Aaron |date=December 30, 2005}}</ref> Frankena also argued that ''naturalistic fallacy'' is a complete misnomer because it is neither limited to naturalistic properties nor necessarily a fallacy. On the first word (''naturalistic''), he noted that Moore rejected defining ''good'' in non-natural as well as natural terms.<ref name="Hamid">{{cite book |pages=93β96 |title=G.E. Moore: A Study of His Ethics |last=Hamid |first=Md. Abdul |isbn=978-81-7099-174-8 |publisher=Mittal Publications |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=lxnsElfqa70C&pg=PA94 |year=1989}}</ref> Frankena rejected the idea that the second word (''fallacy'') represented an error in [[reasoning]] – a fallacy as it is usually recognized – rather than an error in [[semantics]].<ref name="Ridge">{{cite encyclopedia |encyclopedia=Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |last=Ridge |first=Michael |title=Moral Non-Naturalism |date=June 26, 2008 |accessdate=March 31, 2011 |editor=Edward N. Zalta |url=http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/moral-non-naturalism/}}</ref> In Moore's [[open-question argument]], because questions such as "Is that which is pleasurable good?" have no definitive answer, then pleasurable is not synonymous with good. Frankena rejected this argument as: the fact that there is always an open question merely reflects the fact that it makes sense to ask whether two things that may be identical in fact are.<ref name="Flew">{{cite encyclopedia |title=Definist fallacy |encyclopedia=A Dictionary of Philosophy |page=85 |last=Flew |first=Antony |author-link=Antony Flew |year=1984 |publisher=Macmillan |isbn=978-0-312-20923-0 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=MmJHVU9Rv3YC&pg=PA85}}</ref> Thus, even if good ''were'' identical to pleasurable, it makes sense to ask whether it is; the answer may be "yes", but the question was legitimate. This seems to contradict Moore's view which accepts that sometimes alternative answers could be dismissed without argument; however, Frankena objects that this{{what|date=December 2024}} would be committing the fallacy of [[begging the question]].<ref name="Ridge"/>
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)