Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Intuitionistic logic
(section)
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
====Existential vs. universal quantification==== Firstly, when <math>x</math> is not free in the proposition <math>\varphi</math>, then :<math>\big(\exists x\, (\phi(x)\to \varphi)\big)\,\,\to\,\,\Big(\big(\forall x \ \phi(x)\big)\to\varphi\Big)</math> When the [[domain of discourse]] is empty, then by the [[principle of explosion]], an existential statement implies anything. When the domain contains at least one term, then assuming excluded middle for <math>\forall x \, \phi(x)</math>, the inverse of the above implication becomes provably too, meaning the two sides become equivalent. This inverse direction is equivalent to the [[drinker's paradox]] (DP). Moreover, an existential and dual variant of it is given by the [[independence of premise]] principle (IP). Classically, the statement above is moreover equivalent to a more disjunctive form discussed further below. Constructively, existence claims are however generally harder to come by. If the domain of discourse is not empty and <math>\phi</math> is moreover independent of <math>x</math>, such principles are equivalent to formulas in the propositional calculus. Here, the formula then just expresses the identity <math>(\phi\to\varphi)\to(\phi\to\varphi)</math>. This is the [[currying|curried]] form of [[modus ponens]] <math>((\phi\to\varphi)\land\phi)\to\varphi</math>, which in the special the case with <math>\varphi</math> as a false proposition results in the [[law of non-contradiction]] principle <math>\neg(\phi\land\neg\phi)</math>. Considering a false proposition <math>\varphi</math> for the original implication results in the important * <math>(\exists x \ \neg \phi(x)) \to \neg (\forall x \ \phi(x))</math> In words: "If there exists an entity <math>x</math> that does ''not'' have the property <math>\phi</math>, then the following is ''refuted'': Each entity has the property <math>\phi</math>." The quantifier formula with negations also immediately follows from the non-contradiction principle derived above, each instance of which itself already follows from the more particular <math>\neg(\neg\neg\phi\land\neg\phi)</math>. To derive a contradiction given <math>\neg\phi</math>, it suffices to establish its negation <math>\neg\neg\phi</math> (as opposed to the stronger <math>\phi</math>) and this makes proving double-negations valuable also. By the same token, the original quantifier formula in fact still holds with <math>\forall x \ \phi(x)</math> weakened to <math>\forall x \big((\phi(x)\to\varphi)\to\varphi\big)</math>. And so, in fact, a stronger theorem holds: :<math>(\exists x \ \neg \phi(x)) \to \neg (\forall x \, \neg\neg\phi(x))</math> In words: "If there exists an entity <math>x</math> that does ''not'' have the property <math>\phi</math>, then the following is ''refuted'': For each entity, one is ''not'' able to prove that it does ''not'' have the property <math>\phi</math>". Secondly, :<math>\big(\forall x \, (\phi(x)\to \varphi)\big)\,\,\leftrightarrow\,\,\big((\exists x \ \phi(x))\to\varphi\big)</math> where similar considerations apply. Here the existential part is always a hypothesis and this is an equivalence. Considering the special case again, * <math>(\forall x \ \neg \phi(x)) \leftrightarrow \neg (\exists x \ \phi(x))</math> The proven conversion <math>(\chi\to\neg \phi)\leftrightarrow(\phi\to\neg \chi)</math> can be used to obtain two further implications: :<math>(\forall x \ \phi(x)) \to \neg (\exists x \ \neg \phi(x))</math> :<math>(\exists x \ \phi(x)) \to \neg (\forall x \ \neg \phi(x))</math> Of course, variants of such formulas can also be derived that have the double-negations in the antecedent. A special case of the first formula here is <math>(\forall x \, \neg\phi(x)) \to \neg (\exists x \, \neg \neg \phi(x))</math> and this is indeed stronger than the <math>\to</math>-direction of the equivalence bullet point listed above. For simplicity of the discussion here and below, the formulas are generally presented in weakened forms without all possible insertions of double-negations in the antecedents. More general variants hold. Incorporating the predicate <math>\psi</math> and currying, the following generalization also entails the relation between implication and conjunction in the predicate calculus, discussed below. :<math>\big(\forall x \ \phi(x)\to (\psi(x)\to\varphi)\big)\,\,\leftrightarrow\,\,\Big(\big(\exists x \ \phi(x)\land \psi(x)\big)\to\varphi\Big)</math> If the predicate <math>\psi</math> is decidedly false for all <math>x</math>, then this equivalence is trivial. If <math>\psi</math> is decidedly true for all <math>x</math>, the schema simply reduces to the previously stated equivalence. In the language of [[Constructive_set_theory#Classes|classes]], <math>A=\{x\mid\phi(x)\}</math> and <math>B=\{x\mid\psi(x)\}</math>, the special case of this equivalence with false <math>\varphi</math> equates two characterizations of [[Disjoint sets|disjointness]] <math>A\cap B=\emptyset</math>: :<math>\forall(x\in A).x\notin B\,\,\leftrightarrow\,\,\neg\exists(x\in A).x\in B</math>
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)