Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Musical analysis
(section)
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
==Divergent analyses== {{Overly detailed|date=September 2015|section=yes}} Typically a given work is analyzed by more than one person and different or divergent analyses are created. For instance, the first two bars of the prelude to [[Claude Debussy]]'s ''[[Pelléas et Mélisande (opera)|Pelléas et Mélisande]]'': [[File:Debussy Pelleas et Melisande prelude opening.PNG|400px|thumb|center|Debussy ''Pelléas et Mélisande'' prelude opening[[File:Debussy Pelleas et Melisande-prelude opening.mid]]]] are analyzed differently by Leibowitz{{sfn|Leibowitz|1971}} Laloy,{{sfn|Laloy|1902}} van Appledorn,{{sfn|van Appeldorn|1966}} and Christ.{{sfn|Christ|1966}} Leibowitz analyses this succession harmonically as D minor:I–VII–V, ignoring melodic motion, Laloy analyses the succession as D:I–V, seeing the G in the second measure as an [[musical ornamentation|ornament]], and both van Appledorn and Christ{{sfn|Christ|1966|loc={{Page needed|date=September 2015}}}} analyses the succession as D:I–VII. Nattiez{{sfn|Nattiez|1990|loc=173}} argues that this divergence is due to the analysts' respective analytic situations, and to what he calls transcendent principles (1997b: 853, what George Holton might call "themata"), the "philosophical project[s]", "underlying principles", or a prioris of analyses, one example being Nattiez's use of the tripartitional definition of ''[[sign (semiotics)|sign]]'', and what, after [[epistemological]] historian Paul Veyne, he calls ''plots''. Van Appledorn sees the succession as D:I–VII so as to allow the interpretation of the first chord in [[bar (music)|measure]] five, which Laloy sees as a dominant seventh on D (V/IV) with a diminished fifth (despite that the IV doesn't arrive till measure twelve), while van Appledorn sees it as a French sixth on D, D–F{{music|sharp}}–A{{music|b}}–[C] in the usual second inversion. This means that D is the second degree and the required reference to the first degree, C, being established by the D:VII or C major [[chord (music)|chord]]. "The ''need to explain'' the chord in measure five establishes that C–E–G is 'equally important' as the D–(F)–A of measure one." Leibowitz{{sfn|Leibowitz|1971|loc={{Page needed|date=September 2015}}}} gives only the bass for chord, E indicating the progression I–II an "unreal" progression in keeping with his "[[dialectic]] between the real and the unreal" used in the analysis, while Christ explains the chord as an augmented eleventh with a bass of B{{Music|flat}}, interpreting it as a traditional tertian [[extended chord]]. [[File:Debussy Pelleas et Melisande prelude 5-6.PNG|400px|thumb|center|Debussy's ''Pélleas et Mélisande'' prelude, measures 5–6[[File:Debussy Pelleas et Melisande prelude 5-6.mid]]]] Not only does an analyst select particular traits, they arrange them according to a plot [intrigue].... Our sense of the component parts of a musical work, like our sense of historical 'facts,' is mediated by lived experience." (176) While John Blacking,{{sfn|Blacking|1973|loc=17–18}} among others, holds that "there is ultimately only one explanation and ... this could be discovered by a context-sensitive analysis of the music in culture," according to Nattiez{{sfn|Nattiez|1990|loc=168}} and others, "there is never ''only one valid'' musical analysis for any given work." Blacking gives as example: "everyone disagrees hotly and stakes his [or her] academic reputation on what [[Mozart]] really meant in this or that bar of his [[symphony|symphonies]], [[concerto]]s, or [[quartet]]s. If we knew exactly what went on inside Mozart's mind when he wrote them, there could be only one explanation". (93) However, Nattiez points out that even if we could determine "what Mozart was thinking" we would still be lacking an analysis of the neutral and esthesic levels. [[Roger Scruton]],{{sfn|Scruton|1978|loc=175–176}} in a review of Nattiez's ''Fondements'', says one may, "describe it as you like so long as you hear it correctly ... certain descriptions suggest wrong ways of hearing it ... what is obvious to hear [in Pélleas et Mélisande] is the contrast in mood and atmosphere between the 'modal' passage and the bars which follow it." Nattiez counters that if compositional intent were identical to perception, "historians of musical language could take a permanent nap.... Scruton sets himself up as a universal, absolute conscience for the 'right' perception of the ''Pélleas et Mélisande''. But hearing is an active symbolic process (which must be explained): ''nothing in perception is self-evident''." Thus Nattiez suggests that analyses, especially those intending "a semiological orientation, should ... at least include a comparative critique of already-written analyses, when they exist, so as to explain why the work has taken on this or that ''image'' constructed by this or that writer: all analysis is a representation; [and] an explanation of the analytical criteria used in the new analysis, so that any critique of this new analysis could be situated in relation to that analysis's own ''objectives'' and ''methods''. As Jean-Claude Gardin so rightly remarks, 'no physicist, no biologist is surprised when asked to indicate, in the context of a new theory, the physical data and the mental operations that led to its formulation'.{{sfn|Gardin|1974|loc=69}}{{incomplete short citation|date=October 2021}} Making one's procedures explicit would help to create a ''cumulative progress in knowledge''." (177){{incomplete short citation|date=October 2021}}
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)