Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Structuralism
(section)
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
== Interpretations and general criticisms ==<!-- This section is linked from [[Jürgen Habermas]], [[Philip Pettit]], [[Paul Ricœur]] and [[Cornelius Castoriadis]] --> Structuralism is less popular today than other approaches, such as [[post-structuralism]] and [[deconstruction]]. Structuralism has often been criticized for being ahistorical and for favouring [[Determinism|deterministic]] structural forces over the [[Agency (philosophy)|ability of people to act]]. As the political turbulence of the 1960s and 1970s (particularly the [[Protests of 1968|student uprisings of May 1968]]) began affecting academia, issues of power and political struggle moved to the center of public attention.<ref>Marshall, J. D., ed. 2004. [https://books.google.com/books?id=rwDR3oSoWWAC ''Poststructuralism, Philosophy, Pedagogy'']. Springer. p. xviii.</ref> In the 1980s, [[deconstruction]]—and its emphasis on the fundamental ambiguity of language rather than its logical structure—became popular. By the end of the century, structuralism was seen as a historically important [[school of thought]], but the movements that it spawned, rather than structuralism itself, commanded attention.<ref>[[Alan Finlayson|Finlayson, Alan]], and Jeremy Valentine. 2002. [https://books.google.com/books?id=dQMQAQAAIAAJ ''Politics and post-structuralism: an introduction'']. Edinburgh University Press. p. 8.</ref> Several social theorists and academics have strongly criticized structuralism or even dismissed it. French [[hermeneutic]] philosopher [[Paul Ricœur]] (1969) criticized Lévi-Strauss for overstepping the limits of [[Validity (logic)|validity]] of the structuralist approach, ending up in what Ricœur described as "a [[Kantianism]] without a [[transcendental subject]]."<ref>[[Paul Ricœur|Ricœur, Paul]]. [1969] 2004. ''The Conflict of Interpretations: Essays in Hermeneutics'' [''Le conflit des interprétations: Essais d’herméneutique'']. [[Continuum Publishing|Continuum]]. pp. 49, 78ff.</ref> Anthropologist [[Adam Kuper]] (1973) argued that:<ref>[[Adam Kuper|Kuper, Adam]]. 1973. ''Anthropologists and Anthropology: The British School 1922–72''. Penguin. p. 206.</ref><blockquote>'Structuralism' came to have something of the momentum of a millennial movement and some of its adherents felt that they formed a [[secret society]] of the seeing in a world of the blind. Conversion was not just a matter of accepting a new paradigm. It was, almost, a question of salvation. </blockquote>[[Philip Noel Pettit]] (1975) called for an abandoning of "the [[Positivism|positivist]] dream which Lévi-Strauss dreamed for [[semiology]]," arguing that semiology is not to be placed among the [[natural sciences]].<ref>[[Philip Pettit|Pettit, Philip]]. 1975. [https://books.google.com/books?id=lQ5n3czwdZQC ''The Concept of Structuralism: A Critical Analysis'']. University of California Press. p. 117.</ref> [[Cornelius Castoriadis]] (1975) criticized structuralism as failing to explain [[Symbolic system|symbolic mediation]] in the social world;<ref>[[Cornelius Castoriadis|Castoriadis, Cornelius]]. [1975] 1987. ''The Imaginary Institution of Society'' [''L'institution imaginaire de la société'']. Cambridge: Polity Press. p. 116–17.</ref> he viewed structuralism as a variation on the "[[Scientific rationalism|logicist]]"<!--[sic]--> theme, arguing that, contrary to what structuralists advocate, language—and symbolic systems in general—cannot be reduced to logical organizations on the basis of the [[Two-valued logic|binary logic]] of [[Square of opposition|oppositions]].<ref>C. Castoriadis (1997), ''The Imaginary: Creation in the Social-Historical Domain''. In: ''World in Fragments''. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 3–18.</ref> [[Critical theorist]] [[Jürgen Habermas]] (1985) accused structuralists like [[Michel Foucault|Foucault]] of being [[Positivism|positivists]]; Foucault, while not an ordinary positivist per se, paradoxically uses the tools of science to criticize science, according to Habermas.<ref>Habermas, J. (1990), ''[[The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity]]'' (originally published in German in 1985 as ''Der Philosophische Diskurs der Moderne''), MIT Press, 1990, p. 276.</ref> (See ''[[Performative contradiction#Usage in philosophy|Performative contradiction]]'' and ''[[Foucault–Habermas debate]]''.) Sociologist [[Anthony Giddens, Baron Giddens|Anthony Giddens]] (1993) is another notable critic; while Giddens draws on a range of structuralist themes in his theorizing, he dismisses the structuralist view that the reproduction of [[social system]]s is merely "a mechanical outcome."<ref>[[Anthony Giddens|Giddens, Anthony]]. 1993. ''New rules of sociological method: A positive critique of interpretative sociologies.'' Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press. p. 121.</ref>
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)