Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Hidden-variable theory
(section)
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
== History == === "God does not play dice" === In June 1926, [[Max Born]] published a paper,<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Born |first=Max |date=1926 |title=Zur Quantenmechanik der Stoßvorgänge |url=http://link.springer.com/10.1007/BF01397477 |journal=Zeitschrift für Physik |language=de |volume=37 |issue=12 |pages=863–867 |doi=10.1007/BF01397477 |bibcode=1926ZPhy...37..863B |s2cid=119896026 |issn=1434-6001}}</ref> in which he was the first to clearly enunciate the probabilistic interpretation of the quantum [[wavefunction|wave function]], which had been introduced by [[Erwin Schrödinger]] earlier in the year. Born concluded the paper as follows:{{blockquote|Here the whole problem of determinism comes up. From the standpoint of our quantum mechanics there is no quantity which in any individual case causally fixes the consequence of the collision; but also experimentally we have so far no reason to believe that there are some inner properties of the atom which conditions a definite outcome for the collision. Ought we to hope later to discover such properties ... and determine them in individual cases? Or ought we to believe that the agreement of theory and experiment—as to the impossibility of prescribing conditions for a causal evolution—is a pre-established harmony founded on the nonexistence of such conditions? I myself am inclined to give up determinism in the world of atoms. But that is a philosophical question for which physical arguments alone are not decisive.}}Born's interpretation of the wave function was criticized by Schrödinger, who had previously attempted to interpret it in real physical terms, but [[Albert Einstein]]'s response became one of the earliest and most famous assertions that quantum mechanics is incomplete:{{blockquote|Quantum mechanics is very worthy of respect. But an inner voice tells me this is not the genuine article after all. The theory delivers much but it hardly brings us closer to the Old One's secret. In any event, I am convinced that ''He'' is not playing dice.<ref name="Einstein letter, 4 Dec 1926">[https://einsteinpapers.press.princeton.edu/vol15-trans/437 The Collected Papers of Albert Einstein, Volume 15: The Berlin Years: Writings & Correspondence, June 1925-May 1927 (English Translation Supplement), p. 403]</ref><ref>{{cite book|title=The Born–Einstein letters: correspondence between Albert Einstein and Max and Hedwig Born from 1916–1955, with commentaries by Max Born|year=1971|publisher=Macmillan|page=91}}</ref>}}[[Niels Bohr]] reportedly replied to Einstein's later expression of this sentiment by advising him to "stop telling God what to do."<ref>This is a common paraphrasing. Bohr recollected his reply to Einstein at the 1927 [[Solvay Congress]] in his essay "Discussion with Einstein on Epistemological Problems in Atomic Physics", in ''Albert Einstein, Philosopher–Scientist'', ed. Paul Arthur Shilpp, Harper, 1949, p. 211: "...in spite of all divergencies of approach and opinion, a most humorous spirit animated the discussions. On his side, Einstein mockingly asked us whether we could really believe that the providential authorities took recourse to dice-playing ("''ob der liebe Gott würfelt''"), to which I replied by pointing at the great caution, already called for by ancient thinkers, in ascribing attributes to Providence in everyday language." Werner Heisenberg, who also attended the congress, recalled the exchange in ''Encounters with Einstein'', Princeton University Press, 1983, p. 117,: "But he [Einstein] still stood by his watchword, which he clothed in the words: 'God does not play at dice.' To which Bohr could only answer: 'But still, it cannot be for us to tell God, how he is to run the world.'"</ref> === Early attempts at hidden-variable theories === Shortly after making his famous "God does not play dice" comment, Einstein attempted to formulate a deterministic counter proposal to quantum mechanics, presenting a paper at a meeting of the [[Prussian Academy of Sciences|Academy of Sciences]] in Berlin, on 5 May 1927, titled "Bestimmt Schrödinger's Wellenmechanik die Bewegung eines Systems vollständig oder nur im Sinne der Statistik?" ("Does Schrödinger's wave mechanics determine the motion of a system completely or only in the statistical sense?").<ref>[https://einsteinpapers.press.princeton.edu/vol15-trans/546 The Collected Papers of Albert Einstein, Volume 15: The Berlin Years: Writings & Correspondence, June 1925-May 1927 (English Translation Supplement), p. 512]</ref><ref>[http://alberteinstein.info/vufind1/Record/EAR000034338 Albert Einstein Archives] reel 2, item 100</ref> However, as the paper was being prepared for publication in the academy's journal, Einstein decided to withdraw it, possibly because he discovered that, contrary to his intention, his use of Schrödinger's field to guide localized particles allowed just the kind of non-local influences he intended to avoid.<ref>{{cite book |last=Baggott |first=Jim |year=2011 |title=The Quantum Story: A History in 40 Moments |url=https://archive.org/details/quantumstoryhist00bagg |url-access=limited |location=New York |publisher=Oxford University Press |pages=[https://archive.org/details/quantumstoryhist00bagg/page/n136 116]–117|isbn=978-0-19-956684-6 }}</ref> At the [[Solvay Conference#Fifth Conference|Fifth Solvay Congress]], held in Belgium in October 1927 and attended by all the major theoretical physicists of the era, [[Louis de Broglie]] presented [[Pilot wave theory|his own version of a deterministic hidden-variable theory]], apparently unaware of Einstein's aborted attempt earlier in the year. In his theory, every particle had an associated, hidden "pilot wave" which served to guide its trajectory through space. The theory was subject to criticism at the Congress, particularly by [[Wolfgang Pauli]], which de Broglie did not adequately answer; de Broglie abandoned the theory shortly thereafter. === Declaration of completeness of quantum mechanics, and the Bohr–Einstein debates === {{Main|Bohr–Einstein debates}} Also at the Fifth Solvay Congress, Max Born and [[Werner Heisenberg]] made a presentation summarizing the recent tremendous theoretical development of quantum mechanics. At the conclusion of the presentation, they declared:{{blockquote|[W]hile we consider ... a quantum mechanical treatment of the electromagnetic field ... as not yet finished, we consider quantum mechanics to be a closed theory, whose fundamental physical and mathematical assumptions are no longer susceptible of any modification... On the question of the 'validity of the law of causality' we have this opinion: as long as one takes into account only experiments that lie in the domain of our currently acquired physical and quantum mechanical experience, the assumption of indeterminism in principle, here taken as fundamental, agrees with experience.<ref>Max Born and Werner Heisenberg, "Quantum mechanics", proceedings of the Fifth Solvay Congress.</ref>}}Although there is no record of Einstein responding to Born and Heisenberg during the technical sessions of the Fifth Solvay Congress, he did challenge the completeness of quantum mechanics at various times. In his tribute article for Born's retirement he discussed the quantum representation of a macroscopic ball bouncing elastically between rigid barriers. He argues that such a quantum representation does not represent a specific ball, but "time ensemble of systems". As such the representation is correct, but incomplete because it does not represent the real individual macroscopic case.<ref>{{Cite arXiv |last=Einstein |first=Albert |title=Elementary Considerations on the Interpretation of the Foundations of Quantum Mechanics |date=2011 |class=physics.hist-ph |eprint=1107.3701 |quote=This paper, whose original title was “Elementare Uberlegungen zur Interpretation ¨ der Grundlagen der Quanten-Mechanik”, has been translated from the German by Dileep Karanth, Department of Physics, University of Wisconsin-Parkside, Kenosha, USA}}</ref> Einstein considered quantum mechanics incomplete "because the state function, in general, does not even describe the individual event/system".<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Ballentine |first=L. E. |date=1972-12-01 |title=Einstein's Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics |journal=American Journal of Physics |language=en |volume=40 |issue=12 |pages=1763–1771 |doi=10.1119/1.1987060 |bibcode=1972AmJPh..40.1763B |issn=0002-9505|doi-access=free }}</ref> === Von Neumann's proof === [[John von Neumann]] in his 1932 book ''[[Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics]]'' had presented a [[Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics#No hidden variables proof|proof]] that there could be no "hidden parameters" in quantum mechanics. The validity of von Neumann's proof was questioned by [[Grete Hermann]] in 1935, who found a flaw in the proof. The critical issue concerned averages over ensembles. Von Neumann assumed that a relation between the [[expected value]]s of different observable quantities holds for each possible value of the "hidden parameters", rather than only for a statistical average over them.<ref>{{cite book|first=Max |last=Jammer |author-link=Max Jammer |title=The Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics |pages=265–274 |year=1974 |publisher=John Wiley and Sons |isbn=0-471-43958-4}}</ref><ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Mermin |first1=N. David |author-link1=N. David Mermin |last2=Schack |first2=Rüdiger |date=September 2018 |title=Homer Nodded: Von Neumann's Surprising Oversight |journal=Foundations of Physics |language=en |volume=48 |issue=9 |pages=1007–1020 |arxiv=1805.10311 |bibcode=2018FoPh...48.1007M |doi=10.1007/s10701-018-0197-5 |issn=0015-9018 |doi-access=free}}</ref> However Hermann's work went mostly unnoticed until its rediscovery by John Stewart Bell more than 30 years later.<ref>Hermann, G.: Die naturphilosophischen Grundlagen der Quantenmechanik (Auszug). Abhandlungen der Fries’schen Schule 6, 75–152 (1935). English translation: Chapter 15 of “Grete Hermann — Between physics and philosophy”, Elise Crull and Guido Bacciagaluppi, eds., Springer, 2016, 239- 278. [Volume 42 of Studies in History and Philosophy of Science]</ref><ref>{{Cite journal |last=Del Santo |first=Flavio |date=2022-01-02 |title=Beyond Method: The Diatribe Between Feyerabend and Popper Over the Foundations of Quantum Mechanics |journal=International Studies in the Philosophy of Science |language=en |volume=35 |issue=1 |pages=5–22 |arxiv=2108.13121 |doi=10.1080/02698595.2022.2031430}}</ref> The validity and definitiveness of von Neumann's proof were also questioned by [[Hans Reichenbach]], and possibly in conversation though not in print by Albert Einstein. Reportedly, in a conversation circa 1938 with his assistants [[Peter Bergmann]] and [[Valentine Bargmann]], Einstein pulled von Neumann's book off his shelf, pointed to the same assumption critiqued by Hermann and Bell, and asked why one should believe in it.<ref>{{cite book|first=Hans |last=Reichenbach |author-link=Hans Reichenbach |title=Philosophic Foundations of Quantum Mechanics |year=1944 |publisher=University of California Press |page=14 |oclc=872622725}}</ref><ref>{{cite book|last=Wick|first=David|chapter=Bell's Theorem |year=1995|title=The Infamous Boundary: Seven Decades of Heresy in Quantum Physics |publisher=Springer |location=New York|doi=10.1007/978-1-4612-4030-3_11|isbn=978-0-387-94726-6 |page=286}}</ref> [[Simon B. Kochen|Simon Kochen]] and [[Ernst Specker]] rejected von Neumann's key assumption as early as 1961, but did not publish a criticism of it until 1967.<ref>{{Cite book |author-first1=John |author-last1=Conway |author-link1=John Horton Conway |author-first2=Simon |author-last2=Kochen |author-link2=Simon B. Kochen |chapter=The Geometry of the Quantum Paradoxes |pages=257–269 |title=Quantum [Un]speakables: From Bell to Quantum Information |date=2002 |publisher=Springer |editor-first1=Reinhold A. |editor-last1=Bertlmann |editor-link1=Reinhold Bertlmann |editor-first2=Anton |editor-last2=Zeilinger |editor-link2=Anton Zeilinger |isbn=3-540-42756-2 |location=Berlin |oclc=49404213}}</ref> === EPR paradox === {{Main|EPR paradox}} Einstein argued that quantum mechanics could not be a complete theory of physical reality. He wrote, {{blockquote|Consider a mechanical system consisting of two partial systems ''A'' and ''B'' which interact with each other only during a limited time. Let the ''ψ'' function [i.e., [[wavefunction]]] before their interaction be given. Then the Schrödinger equation will furnish the ''ψ'' function after the interaction has taken place. Let us now determine the physical state of the partial system ''A'' as completely as possible by measurements. Then quantum mechanics allows us to determine the ''ψ'' function of the partial system ''B'' from the measurements made, and from the ''ψ'' function of the total system. This determination, however, gives a result which depends upon which of the physical quantities (observables) of ''A'' have been measured (for instance, coordinates or momenta). Since there can be only one physical state of ''B'' after the interaction which cannot reasonably be considered to depend on the particular measurement we perform on the system ''A'' separated from ''B'' it may be concluded that the ''ψ'' function is not unambiguously coordinated to the physical state. This coordination of several ''ψ'' functions to the same physical state of system ''B'' shows again that the ''ψ'' function cannot be interpreted as a (complete) description of a physical state of a single system.<ref>{{Cite journal |author=Einstein A |year=1936 |title=Physics and Reality |journal=Journal of the Franklin Institute |volume=221|issue=3 |page=349 |doi=10.1016/S0016-0032(36)91047-5 |bibcode=1936FrInJ.221..349E }}</ref>}} Together with [[Boris Podolsky]] and [[Nathan Rosen]], Einstein published a paper that gave a related but distinct argument against the completeness of quantum mechanics.<ref>{{Cite journal |first1=A. |last1=Einstein |first2=B. |last2=Podolsky |first3=N. |last3=Rosen |year=1935 |title=Can Quantum-Mechanical Description of Physical Reality Be Considered Complete? |journal=Physical Review |volume=47 |issue= 10|pages=777–780 |doi=10.1103/physrev.47.777 |bibcode=1935PhRv...47..777E |doi-access=free }}</ref> They proposed a [[thought experiment]] involving a pair of particles prepared in what would later become known as an [[Quantum entanglement|entangled]] [[quantum state|state]]. Einstein, Podolsky, and Rosen pointed out that, in this state, if the position of the first particle were measured, the result of measuring the position of the second particle could be predicted. If instead the momentum of the first particle were measured, then the result of measuring the momentum of the second particle could be predicted. They argued that no action taken on the first particle could instantaneously affect the other, since this would involve information being transmitted faster than light, which is impossible according to the [[theory of relativity]]. They invoked a principle, later known as the "EPR criterion of reality", positing that: "If, without in any way disturbing a system, we can predict with certainty (i.e., with [[probability]] equal to unity) the value of a physical quantity, then there exists an element of reality corresponding to that quantity." From this, they inferred that the second particle must have a definite value of both position and of momentum prior to either quantity being measured. But quantum mechanics considers these two observables [[Observable#Incompatibility of observables in quantum mechanics|incompatible]] and thus does not associate simultaneous values for both to any system. Einstein, Podolsky, and Rosen therefore concluded that quantum theory does not provide a complete description of reality.<ref>{{cite book |last=Peres |first=Asher |author-link=Asher Peres |title=Quantum Theory: Concepts and Methods |title-link=Quantum Theory: Concepts and Methods |pages=149 |publisher=Kluwer |year=2002}}</ref> Bohr answered the Einstein–Podolsky–Rosen challenge as follows: {{blockquote|[The argument of] Einstein, Podolsky and Rosen contains an ambiguity as regards the meaning of the expression "without in any way disturbing a system." ... [E]ven at this stage [i.e., the measurement of, for example, a particle that is part of an entangled pair], there is essentially the question of an influence on the very conditions which define the possible types of predictions regarding the future behavior of the system. Since these conditions constitute an inherent element of the description of any phenomenon to which the term "physical reality" can be properly attached, we see that the argumentation of the mentioned authors does not justify their conclusion that quantum-mechanical description is essentially incomplete."<ref>{{Cite journal |author=Bohr N |year=1935 |title=Can Quantum-Mechanical Description of Physical Reality be Considered Complete? |journal=Physical Review |volume=48 |issue=8 |pages=700 |doi=10.1103/physrev.48.696|bibcode = 1935PhRv...48..696B |doi-access=free }}</ref>}} Bohr is here choosing to define a "physical reality" as limited to a phenomenon that is immediately observable by an arbitrarily chosen and explicitly specified technique, using his own special definition of the term 'phenomenon'. He wrote in 1948: {{blockquote|As a more appropriate way of expression, one may strongly advocate limitation of the use of the word ''phenomenon'' to refer exclusively to observations obtained under specified circumstances, including an account of the whole experiment.<ref>{{cite journal | author = Bohr N. | author-link = Niels Bohr | year = 1948 | title = On the notions of causality and complementarity | journal = Dialectica | volume = 2 | issue = 3–4| pages = 312–319 [317] | doi=10.1111/j.1746-8361.1948.tb00703.x}}</ref><ref>[[Léon Rosenfeld|Rosenfeld, L.]] (). 'Niels Bohr's contribution to epistemology', pp. 522–535 in ''Selected Papers of Léon Rosenfeld'', Cohen, R.S., Stachel, J.J. (editors), D. Riedel, Dordrecht, {{ISBN|978-90-277-0652-2}}, p. 531: "Moreover, the complete definition of the phenomenon must essentially contain the indication of some permanent mark left upon a recording device which is part of the apparatus; only by thus envisaging the phenomenon as a closed event, terminated by a permanent record, can we do justice to the typical wholeness of the quantal processes."</ref>}} This was, of course, in conflict with the EPR criterion of reality. === Bell's theorem === {{Main|Bell's theorem}} In 1964, [[John Stewart Bell]] showed through his famous theorem that if local hidden variables exist, certain experiments could be performed involving quantum entanglement where the result would satisfy a [[Bell's theorem|Bell inequality]]. If, on the other hand, statistical correlations resulting from quantum entanglement could not be explained by local hidden variables, the Bell inequality would be violated. Another [[no-go theorem]] concerning hidden-variable theories is the [[Kochen–Specker theorem]]. Physicists such as [[Alain Aspect]] and Paul Kwiat have performed [[Bell test experiments|experiments]] that have found violations of these inequalities up to 242 standard deviations.<ref>{{cite journal | author = Kwiat P. G.|display-authors=etal | year = 1999 | title = Ultrabright source of polarization-entangled photons | journal = Physical Review A | volume = 60 | issue = 2| pages = R773–R776 | doi=10.1103/physreva.60.r773 | bibcode=1999PhRvA..60..773K| arxiv = quant-ph/9810003 |s2cid=16417960 }}</ref> This rules out local hidden-variable theories, but does not rule out non-local ones. Theoretically, there could be [[Bell test loopholes|experimental problems]] that affect the validity of the experimental findings. [[Gerard 't Hooft]] has disputed the validity of Bell's theorem on the basis of the [[superdeterminism]] loophole and proposed some ideas to construct local deterministic models.<ref>{{cite arXiv | eprint=quant-ph/0701097 | author1=Gerard 't Hooft | title=The Free-Will Postulate in Quantum Mechanics | date=2007 }}</ref><ref>{{cite arXiv | eprint=0908.3408 | author1=Gerard 't Hooft | title=Entangled quantum states in a local deterministic theory | date=2009 | class=quant-ph }}</ref>
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)