Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Nominalism
(section)
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
===Ancient Greek philosophy=== [[Plato]] was perhaps the first writer in [[Western philosophy]] to clearly state a [[Realism (philosophy)|realist]], i.e., non-nominalist, position: <blockquote>... We customarily hypothesize a single form in connection with each of the many things to which we apply the same name. ... For example, there are many beds and tables. ... But there are only two forms of such furniture, one of the bed and one of the table. ([[The Republic (Plato)|''Republic'']] 596aβb, trans. Grube) </blockquote> <blockquote>What about someone who believes in beautiful things, but doesn't believe in the beautiful itself ...? Don't you think he is living in a dream rather than a wakened state? (''Republic'' 476c)</blockquote> The Platonic universals corresponding to the names "bed" and "beautiful" were the [[Theory of Forms|Form]] of the Bed and the Form of the Beautiful, or the ''Bed Itself'' and the ''Beautiful Itself''. Platonic Forms were the first universals posited as such in philosophy.<ref name="Penner 1987, p. 24">Penner (1987), p. 24.</ref> Our term "universal" is due to the English translation of [[Aristotle]]'s technical term ''katholou'' which he coined specially for the purpose of discussing the problem of universals.<ref>Peters (1967), p. 100.</ref> ''Katholou'' is a contraction of the phrase ''kata holou'', meaning "on the whole".<ref>[http://archimedes.fas.harvard.edu/cgi-bin/dict?name=lsj&lang=el&word=kaqo%2flou&filter=GreekXlit "katholou"] in [[Harvard]]'s Archimedes Project online version of [[Henry Liddell|Liddell]] & [[Robert Scott (philologist)|Scott]]'s ''[[A Greek-English Lexicon]]''.</ref> Aristotle famously rejected certain aspects of Plato's Theory of Forms, but he clearly rejected nominalism as well: <blockquote>... 'Man', and indeed every general predicate, signifies not an individual, but some quality, or quantity or relation, or something of that sort. (''[[Sophistical Refutations]]'' xxii, 178b37, trans. Pickard-Cambridge)</blockquote> The first philosophers to explicitly describe nominalist arguments were the [[Stoics]], especially [[Chrysippus]].<ref>John Sellars, ''Stoicism'', Routledge, 2014, pp. 84β85: "[Stoics] have often been presented as the first nominalists, rejecting the existence of universal concepts altogether. ... For Chrysippus there are no universal entities, whether they be conceived as substantial [[Platonic Forms]] or in some other manner."</ref><ref>{{cite web| url = https://www.iep.utm.edu/chrysipp/| title = Chrysippus (Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy)}}</ref>
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)