Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Rigid designator
(section)
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
==Proper names and definite descriptions== The notion of absolute concepts was then revived by [[Saul Kripke]], with the name “rigid designation”, in the lectures that became ''[[Naming and Necessity]]'', in the course of his argument against [[Descriptivist theory of names|descriptivist]] theories of reference, building on the work of [[Ruth Barcan Marcus]]. At the time of Kripke's lectures, the dominant theory of reference in [[analytic philosophy]] (associated with the theories of [[Gottlob Frege]] and [[Bertrand Russell]]) was that the meaning of sentences involving proper names could be given by substituting a contextually appropriate description for the name. Russell,<ref>Russell, Bertrand (1917), ''Knowledge by Acquaintance and Knowledge by Description''</ref> for example, famously held that someone who had never met [[Otto von Bismarck]] might know of him as ''the first [[Chancellor of Germany|Chancellor of the German Empire]]'', and if so, his statement that (say) "Bismarck was a ruthless politician" should be understood to mean "The first Chancellor of the German Empire was a ruthless politician" (which could in turn be analysed into a series of more basic statements according to the method Russell introduced in his theory of [[definite descriptions]]). Kripke argued—against both the Russellian analysis and several attempted refinements of it—that such descriptions could not possibly ''mean the same thing'' as the name "Bismarck," on the grounds that proper names such as "Bismarck" always designate ''rigidly'', whereas descriptions such as "the first Chancellor of the German Empire" do not. Thus, for example, it ''might have been the case'' that Bismarck died in infancy. If so, he would not have ever satisfied the description "the first Chancellor of the German Empire," and (indeed) someone else probably would have. It does not follow that the first Chancellor of the German Empire may not have been the first Chancellor of the German Empire—that is (at least according to its surface-structure) a contradiction. Kripke argues that the way that proper names ''work'' is that when we make statements about what might or might not have been true of Bismarck, we are talking about what might or might not have been true of ''that particular person'' in various situations, whereas when we make statements about what might or might not have been true of, say, ''the first Chancellor of the German Empire'' we ''could'' be talking about what might or might not have been true of ''whoever'' would have happened to fill that office in those situations. The "could" here is important to note: rigid designation is a property of the ''way terms are used'', not a property of ''the terms themselves'', and some philosophers, following [[Keith Donnellan]], have argued that a phrase such as "the first Chancellor of the German Empire" ''could'' be used rigidly, in sentences such as "the first Chancellor of the German Empire could have decided never to go into politics." Kripke himself doubted that there was any need to recognize rigid uses of definite descriptions, and argued that [[Bertrand Russell|Russell]]'s notion of [[scope (logic)|scope]] offered all that was needed to account for such sentences. But in either case, Kripke argued, nothing important in his account depends on the question. Whether definite descriptions can be used rigidly or not, they can at least ''sometimes'' be used non-rigidly, but a proper name ''can only be used rigidly''; the asymmetry, Kripke argues, demonstrates that no definite description could ''give the meaning'' of a proper name—although it might be used to explain ''who'' a name refers to (that is, to "fix the referent" of the name).
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)