Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Self-deception
(section)
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
==Theorization== ===Analysis=== The traditional paradigm of self-deception is modeled after ''interpersonal'' deception, where ''A'' intentionally gets ''B'' to believe some proposition ''p'', all the while knowing or believing truly ¬''p'' (not ''p'').<ref name="stanford"/> Such deception is intentional and requires the deceiver to know or believe ¬''p'' and the deceived to believe ''p''. On this traditional mode, self-deceivers must (1) hold contradictory beliefs and (2) intentionally get themselves to hold a belief they know or believe truly to be false.<ref name="stanford">{{Cite SEP |url-id=self-deception |title=Self-Deception |last=Deweese-Boyd|first= Ian}}</ref> The process of [[rationalization (psychology)|rationalization]], however, can obscure the intent of self-deception. Brian McLaughlin illustrates that such rationalizations in certain circumstances permit the phenomenon. When a person, who disbelieves ''p'', intentionally tries to make himself believe or continue believing ''p'' by engaging in such activities, and, as a result unintentionally misleads himself into believing or continuing to believe ''p'' via biased thinking, he deceives himself in a way appropriate for self-deception. No deceitful intention is required for this.<ref>"Exploring the Possibility of Self-Deception in Belief" by Brian P. McLaughlin. [[PhilPapers]]: [http://philpapers.org/rec/MCLETP MCLETP]</ref> ===Psychology=== Self-deception calls into question the nature of the individual, specifically in a [[psychology|psychological]] context and the nature of "self". Irrationality is the foundation from which the argued paradoxes of self-deception stem, and it is argued{{By whom|date=March 2021}} that not everyone has the "special talents" and capacities for self-deception.<ref>"The Deceptive Self: Liars, Layers, and Lairs" by Amélie Oksenberg Rorty. [[PhilPapers]]: [http://philpapers.org/rec/RORTDS-2 RORTDS-2]</ref> However, rationalization is influenced by myriad factors, including socialization, personal biases, fear, and cognitive repression. Such rationalization can be manipulated in both positive and negative fashions; convincing one to perceive a negative situation optimistically and vice versa. In contrast, rationalization alone cannot effectively clarify the dynamics of self-deception, as reason is just one adaptive form mental processes can take.<ref>{{cite book|last1=Johnston|first1=Mark|title=Philosophy of Psychology: Debates on Psychological Explanation|date=1995|publisher=Blackwell|location=Cambridge|pages=63–91|chapter=Self-Deception and the Nature of Mind}} [[PhilPapers]]: [http://philpapers.org/rec/JOHSAT JOHSAT]</ref> ===Paradoxes=== The works of philosopher [[Alfred Mele|Alfred R. Mele]] have provided insight into some of the more prominent paradoxes regarding self-deception. Two of these paradoxes include the self-deceiver's state of mind and the dynamics of self-deception, coined the "static" paradox and the "dynamic/strategic" paradox, respectively. Mele formulates an example of the "static" paradox as the following: <blockquote>If ever a person ''A'' deceives a person ''B'' into believing that something, ''p'', is true, ''A'' knows or truly believes that ''p'' is false while causing ''B'' to believe that ''p'' is true. So when ''A'' deceives ''A'' (i.e., himself) into believing that ''p'' is true, he knows or truly believes that ''p'' is false while causing himself to believe that ''p'' is true. Thus, ''A'' must simultaneously believe that ''p'' is false and believe that ''p'' is true. But how is this possible?<ref name="Mele">''Two Paradoxes of Self-Deception'' by Alfred R. Mele. [[PhilPapers]]: [http://philpapers.org/rec/MELTPO-5 MELTPO-5]</ref></blockquote> Mele then describes the "dynamic/strategy" paradox: <blockquote>In general, ''A'' cannot successfully employ a deceptive strategy against ''B'' if ''B'' knows ''A'''s intention and plan. This seems plausible as well when ''A'' and ''B'' are the same person. A potential self-deceiver's knowledge of his intention and strategy would seem typically to render them ineffective. On the other hand, the suggestion that self-deceivers typically successfully execute their self-deceptive strategies without knowing what they are up to may seem absurd; for an agent's effective execution of his plans seems generally to depend on his cognizance of them and their goals. So how, in general, can an agent deceive himself by employing a self-deceptive strategy?<ref name="Mele"/></blockquote> These models call into question how one can simultaneously hold contradictory beliefs ("static" paradox) and deceive oneself without rendering one's intentions ineffective ("dynamic/strategic" paradox). Attempts at a resolution to these have created two schools of thought: one that maintains that paradigmatic cases of self-deception are intentional and one that denies the notion—''intentionalists'' and ''non-intentionalists'', respectively.<ref name="stanford"/> Intentionalists tend to agree that self-deception is intentional, but divide over whether it requires the holding of contradictory beliefs.<ref name="stanford"/> This school of thought incorporates elements of temporal partitioning (extended over time to benefit the self-deceiver, increasing the chance of forgetting the deception altogether) and psychological partitioning (incorporating various aspects of the "self"). Non-intentionalists, in contrast, tend to believe that cases of self-deception are not necessarily accidental, but motivated by desire, anxiety, or some other emotion regarding ''p'' or related to ''p''.<ref name="stanford"/> This notion distinguishes self-deception from misunderstanding. Furthermore, "[[wishful thinking]]" is distinguished from self-deception in that the self-deceivers recognize evidence against their self-deceptive belief or possess, without recognizing, greater counterevidence than wishful thinkers.<ref name="stanford"/> Numerous questions and debates remain in play with respect to the paradoxes of self-deception, and a consensual paradigm has yet to appear. ===Trivers' theory=== It has been theorized that humans are susceptible to self-deception because most people have emotional attachments to beliefs, which in some cases may be [[irrational]]. Some [[evolutionary psychology|evolutionary]] biologists, such as [[Robert Trivers]], have suggested<ref>{{cite book |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=By3I9jsoBQkC |title=Natural Selection and Social Theory: Selected Papers of Robert Trivers |first=Robert |last=Trivers |year=2002 |publisher=Oxford University Press US |isbn=978-0-19-513062-1}}</ref>{{page number needed|date=June 2016}} that [[deception]] plays a significant role in human behavior, and more generally speaking in animal behavior. One deceives oneself to trust something that is not true as to better convince others of that "truth". When a person convinces himself of this untrue thing, they better mask the signs of deception.<ref>{{cite book|chapter=Foreword|first=Robert |last=Trivers |editor-last1=Dawkins|editor-first1=Richard|title=The Selfish Gene|date=1976|publisher=Oxford University Press|chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=WZ9HDAAAQBAJ&pg=PR26|language=en|title-link=The Selfish Gene|isbn=9780191093067 |oclc=2681149}}</ref> Trivers, along with two colleagues ([[Daniel Kriegman]] and Malcolm Slavin), applied his theory of "self-deception in the service of deception" in order to explain how in his view [[Donald Trump]] was able to employ the "[[big lie]]" with such great success.<ref>Kriegman, D., Trivers, R, and Slavin, M. [https://www.rawstory.com/2020/04/leading-psychologists-explain-how-trumps-self-delusions-make-him-stunningly-effective-at-predatory-deception/ "Leading psychologists explain how Trump's self-delusions make him stunningly effective at predatory deception"], ''The Raw Story'', April 6, 2020.</ref> This notion is based on the following [[logic]]: deception is a fundamental aspect of communication in nature, both between and within species. It has evolved so that one can have an advantage over another. From alarm calls to mimicry, animals use deception to further their survival. Those who are better able to perceive deception are more likely to survive. As a result, self-deception behavior evolved to better mask deception from those who perceive it well or, as Trivers puts it "hiding the truth from yourself to hide it more deeply from others." In humans, [[awareness]] of the fact that one is acting deceptively often leads to tell-tale signs of deception, such as nostrils flaring, clammy skin, quality and tone of voice, eye movement, or excessive blinking. Therefore, if self-deception enables an individual to believe its own distortions, it will not present such signs of deception, and will therefore appear to be telling the truth. Self-deception can be used both to act greater or lesser than one actually is. For example, one can act overconfident to attract a mate or act under-confident to avoid a threat such as a predator. If an individual is capable of concealing their true feelings and intentions well, then it is more likely to successfully deceive others. It may also be argued that the ability to deceive, or self-deceive, is not the selected trait but rather a by-product of a more primary trait called [[abstract thinking]]. Abstract thinking allows many evolutionary advantages such as more flexible, adaptive behaviors, leading to innovation. Since a lie is an [[abstraction]], the mental process of creating it can only occur in animals with enough brain complexity to permit abstract thinking.<ref>{{Cite journal|last1=Abe|first1=Nobuhito|last2=Okuda|first2=Jiro|last3=Suzuki|first3=Maki|last4=Sasaki|first4=Hiroshi|last5=Matsuda|first5=Tetsuya|last6=Mori|first6=Etsuro|last7=Tsukada|first7=Minoru|last8=Fujii|first8=Toshikatsu|date=December 1, 2008|title=Neural Correlates of True Memory, False Memory, and Deception|journal=Cerebral Cortex|language=en|volume=18|issue=12|pages=2811–2819|doi=10.1093/cercor/bhn037|pmid=18372290|pmc=2583150|issn=1047-3211}}</ref> Moreover, self-deception lowers cognitive cost; that is to say, if one has convinced oneself that that very thing is indeed true, it is less complicated for one to behave or think as that thing was untrue; the mind not thinking constantly of the true thing and then the false thing, but simply being convinced that the false thing is true. ====Evolutionary implications==== Because there is deceit, there exists a strong selection to recognize when deception occurs. As a result, self-deception behavior evolves so as to better hide the signs of deception from others. The presence of deception explains the existence of an innate ability to commit self-deception to hide the indications of deceptions. Humans deceive themselves in order to better deceive others and thus have an advantage over them. In the three decades since Trivers introduced his adaptive theory of self-deception, there has been an ongoing debate over the genetic basis of such a behavior. The explanation of deception and self-deception as innate characteristics is perhaps true, but there are many other explanations for this pattern of behavior. It is possible that the ability to self-deceive is not innate, but a learned trait, acquired through experience. For example, a person could have been caught being deceitful by revealing their knowledge of information they were trying to hide. Their nostrils flared, indicating that they were lying to the other person, and thus did not get what they wanted. Next time, to better achieve success, the person will more actively deceive himself of having knowledge to better hide the signs of deception. Therefore, people could have the capacity to learn self-deception. However, simply because something is learned does not mean that it is not innate; what is learned and what is innate work in conjunction.<ref name="Barkow1995">Barkow, Tooby, & Cosmides. (1995). The Adapted Mind: Evolutionary Psychology and the Generation of Culture.</ref> This is outlined in many introductory textbooks in evolutionary psychology.<ref name="Barkow1995"/> For example, [[preparedness (learning)|preparedness]] occurs in learning to explain why some behaviours are more easily learned than others. Evolutionary psychologists argue that there are learning mechanisms that allow learning to occur.<ref name="Barkow1995"/> ===Medicine=== Self-deception has a prominent role in several medical conditions, such as [[borderline personality disorder]], [[narcissistic personality disorder]], and [[histrionic personality disorder]].<ref name="Ford 1999 p. ">{{cite book | last=Ford | first=Charles | title=Lies!, lies!!, lies!!! : The psychology of deceit | publisher=American Psychiatric Press | location=Washington, DC | year=1999 | isbn=978-0-88048-997-3 | pages=103–125}}</ref>
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)