Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Thing-in-itself
(section)
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
==Criticism== ===F. H. Jacobi=== The first to criticize the concept of a thing-in-itself was [[F. H. Jacobi]], with the expression: {{Blockquote|I could not enter into the system without the assumption of the concept of the thing-in-itself and, on the other hand, I could not remain in it with this concept.<ref>{{Cite book|title=From Critical to Speculative Idealism|last=S. Atlas|pages=21}}</ref>}} ===G. E. Schulze=== The anonymously published work ''[[Aenesidemus (book)|Aenesidemus]]'' was one of the most successful attacks against the project of Kant. According to Kant's teaching, things-in-themselves cannot cause appearances, since the [[Category (Kant)|category]] of [[causality]] can only find application to objects of experience. Kant, therefore, does not have the right to claim the existence of things-in-themselves. This contradiction was subsequently generally accepted as being the main problem of the thing-in-itself. The attack on the thing-in-itself, and the skeptical work in general, had a big impact on [[Fichte]], and [[Schopenhauer]] called [[Gottlob Ernst Schulze|G. E. Schulze]], who was revealed to be the author, “the acutest" of Kant's opponents.<ref name=":0">{{Cite book|title=The World as Will and Representation|last=Schopenhauer|first=Arthur|volume=1 Criticism of the Kantian Philosophy|quote=Kant’s greatest merit is the distinction of the phenomenon from the thing in itself … This defect, as is known, is the introduction of the thing in itself in the way chosen by him, the inadmissibleness of which was exposed at length by G. E. Schulze in "Aenesidemus " and was soon recognised as the untenable point of his system. … It is most remarkable that one of Kant’s opponents, and indeed the acutest of them, G. E. Schulze …}}</ref> ===Johann Gottlieb Fichte=== Initially [[Johann Gottlieb Fichte|Fichte]] embraced [[Kantian philosophy]], including a thing-in-itself, but the work of Schulze made him revise his position. {{Blockquote|Aenesidemus, which I consider one of the most remarkable products of our decade, has convinced me of something which I admittedly already suspected: that even after the labors of Kant and Reinhold, philosophy is still not a science. Aenesidemus has shaken my own system to its very foundations, and, since one cannot live very well under the open sky, I have been forced to construct a new system. I am convinced that philosophy can become a science only if it is generated from one single principle, but that it must then become just as self-evident as geometry.<ref>{{Cite book|title=Fichte: Early Philosophical Writings|publisher=Cornell University Press|year=1993|pages=14}}</ref> }} The system which Fichte subsequently published, ''[[Wissenschaftslehre (Fichte)|Science of Knowledge]]'', scraps the thing-in-itself.<ref>{{Cite book|title=German idealism : the struggle against subjectivism, 1781–1801|year=2002|url=https://archive.org/details/germanidealismst00beis|url-access=limited|last=C. Beiser|first=Frederick|isbn=0-674-00769-7|pages=[https://archive.org/details/germanidealismst00beis/page/n235 217]|publisher=Harvard University Press |quote=First, it eliminates the thing-in-itself and the given manifold.}}</ref> ===Schopenhauer=== In his "[[Critique of the Kantian Philosophy]]" appended to ''[[The World as Will and Representation]]'' (1818), [[Arthur Schopenhauer]] agreed with the critics that the manner in which Kant had introduced the thing-in-itself was inadmissible, but he considered that Kant was right to assert its existence and praised the distinction between thing-in-itself and appearance as Kant's greatest merit.<ref name=":0" /> As he wrote in volume 1 of his ''[[Parerga and Paralipomena]]'', "Fragments of the History of Philosophy," §13: {{Blockquote|Kant was guided by the truth<!--typo here--> certainly felt that there lies behind every phenomenon a being-in-itself whence such phenomenon obtains its existence ... But he undertook to derive this from the given representation itself by the addition of its laws that are known to us ''a priori.'' Yet just because these are ''a priori'', they cannot lead to something independent of, and different from, the phenomenon or representation; and so for this purpose we have to pursue an entirely different course. The inconsistencies in which Kant was involved through the faulty course taken by him in this respect were demonstrated to him by G. E. Schultze who in his ponderous and diffuse manner expounded the matter first anonymously in his ''Aenesidemus'' ... and then in his ''Kritik der theoretischen Philosophie.''<ref>''Parerga and Paralipomena,'' Vol. 1 (1851). Translated by E. F. J. Payne (Oxford, 1974), p. 89-90</ref>}} ===Mainländer=== A unique position is taken by [[Philipp Mainländer]], who hailed Kant for breaking the rules of his own philosophy to proclaim the existence of a thing-in-itself. {{Blockquote|He did it, because he feared nothing more than the allegation, that his philosophy is pure idealism, which makes the whole objective world into illusion and takes away all reality from it. The three remarks of the first part of the [[Prolegomena_to_Any_Future_Metaphysics|''Prolegomena'']] are, with this in mind, very much worth reading. I cannot condemn this great inconsequence. It was the smaller one of two evils, and Kant bravely embraced it.{{#tag:ref|"{{lang|de| Er that es, weil er Nichts mehr fürchtete als den Vorwurf, seine Philosophie sei der reine Idealismus, welcher die ganze objektive Welt zu Schein macht und ihr jede Realität nimmt. Die drei Anmerkungen zum ersten Buche der Prolegomena sind, in dieser Hinsicht, sehr lesenswerth. Diese große Inconsequenz kann ich nicht verdammen. Sie war das kleinere von zwei Uebeln, und Kant ergriff es herzhaft.}}"<ref>{{Cite book|title=Die Philosophie der Erlösung|last=Mainländer|first=Philipp|year=1876|pages=438}}</ref>|group=Note}} }}
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)