Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Unit of selection
(section)
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
== Selection at each level == Below, cases of selection at the genic, cellular, individual and group level from within the multi-level selection perspective are presented and discussed. === Nucleic acid === {{Main article|Gene-centered view of evolution}} {{See also|Missing heritability problem}} [[George C. Williams (biologist)|George C. Williams]] in his influential book ''[[Adaptation and Natural Selection]]'' was one of the first to present a [[gene-centered view of evolution]] with the gene as the unit of selection, arguing that a unit of selection should exhibit a high degree of permanence. [[Richard Dawkins]] has written several books popularizing and expanding the idea. According to Dawkins, genes cause phenotypes and a gene is 'judged' by its phenotypic effects. Dawkins distinguishes entities which survive or fail to survive ("replicators") from entities with temporary existence that interact directly with the environment ("vehicles"). Genes are "replicators" whereas individuals and groups of individuals are "vehicles". Dawkins argues that, although they are both aspects of the same process, "replicators" rather than "vehicles" should be preferred as units of selection. This is because replicators, owing to their permanence, should be regarded as the ultimate beneficiaries of adaptations. Genes are replicators and therefore the gene is the unit of selection. Dawkins further expounded this view in an entire chapter called '[[God's utility function]]' in the book ''[[River Out of Eden]]'' where he explained that genes alone have [[utility function]]s.<ref name="River_Out_of_Eden">See the chapter ''[[God's utility function]]'' in {{cite book | first=Richard | last=Dawkins | author-link=Richard Dawkins | title=River Out of Eden | publisher=Basic Books | year=1995 | isbn=0-465-06990-8| title-link=River Out of Eden }}</ref> Some clear-cut examples of selection at the level of the gene include [[meiotic drive]] and [[retrotransposon]]s. In both of these cases, gene sequences increase their relative frequency in a population without necessarily providing benefits at other levels of organization. Meiotic-drive mutations (see [[segregation distortion]]) manipulate the machinery of chromosomal segregation so that chromosomes carrying the mutation are later found in more than half of the gametes produced by individuals heterozygous for the mutation, and for this reason the frequency of the mutation increases in the population. [[Retrotransposon]]s are DNA sequences that, once replicated by the cellular machinery, insert themselves in the genome more or less randomly. Such insertions can be very mutagenic and thus reduce drastically individual fitness, so that there is strong selection against elements that are very active. Meiotic-drive alleles have also been shown strongly to reduce individual fitness, clearly exemplifying the potential conflict between selection at different levels. According to the [[RNA world]] hypothesis, RNA sequences performing both enzymatic and information storage roles in autocatalytic sets were an early unit of selection and evolution that would later transition into living cells.<ref>{{Cite journal |doi = 10.1186/1745-6150-7-23|pmid = 22793875|pmc = 3495036|title = The RNA world hypothesis: The worst theory of the early evolution of life (except for all the others)a|journal = Biology Direct|volume = 7|pages = 23|year = 2012|last1 = Bernhardt|first1 = Harold S. | doi-access=free }}</ref> It is possible that [[RNA-based evolution]] is still taking place today. Other subcellular entities such as viruses, both [[DNA virus|DNA-based]] and [[RNA virus|RNA-based]], [[Viral evolution|do evolve]]. The gene-centered view of evolution normally refers to selection among different [[allele]]s of the same gene. However, [[gene family|gene families]] also differ in their tendency to diversify and avoid loss during evolution.<ref name="james2023">{{cite journal |last1=James |first1=Jennifer E |last2=Nelson |first2=Paul G |last3=Masel |first3=Joanna |title=Differential Retention of Pfam Domains Contributes to Long-term Evolutionary Trends |journal=Molecular Biology and Evolution |date=4 April 2023 |volume=40 |issue=4 |pages=msad073 |doi=10.1093/molbev/msad073|pmid=36947137 |pmc=10089649 }}</ref> This latter form of selection more closely resembles clade selection of groups of species. === Epigene === {{Main article|Transgenerational epigenetic inheritance|Contribution of epigenetic modifications to evolution}} {{expand section|date=March 2018}} There is also view that evolution is acting on [[epigene]]s.<ref>{{cite journal | author=Hunter, P. | title=Extended phenotype redux. How far can the reach of genes extend in manipulating the environment of an organism? | journal=EMBO Rep | volume=10 | issue=3 | pages=212β5 |pmc=2658563 | pmid=19255576 | doi=10.1038/embor.2009.18| year=2009 }}</ref> === Cell === [[Leo Buss]] in his book ''[[The Evolution of Individuality]]'' proposes that much of the [[Evolutionary developmental biology|evolution of development]] in [[animal]]s reflects the conflict between selective pressures acting at the level of the cell and those acting at the level of the multicellular individual. This perspective can shed new light on phenomena as diverse as [[gastrulation]] and germ line sequestration. This selection for unconstrained proliferation is in conflict with the fitness interests of the individual, and thus there is tension between selection at the level of the cell and selection at the level of the individual. Since the proliferation of specific cells of the vertebrate immune system to fight off infecting pathogens is a case of programmed and exquisitely contained cellular proliferation, it represents a case of the individual manipulating selection at the level of the cell to enhance its own fitness. In the case of the vertebrate immune system, selection at the level of the cell and individual are not in conflict. Some view [[cancer stem cell]]s as units of selection.<ref>{{cite journal | author=Greaves, Mel | volume=6 | issue=1 | title=Cancer stem cells as 'units of selection' | journal=Evolutionary Applications | pages=102β108 |doi=10.1111/eva.12017| pmid=23396760 | pmc=3567475 | year=2013 | bibcode=2013EvApp...6..102G }}</ref> === Behavioural === {{further|Memetics|Dual inheritance theory|Sociocultural evolution|Cultural evolution}} Geneβculture coevolution was developed to explain how human behavior is a product of two different and interacting evolutionary processes: genetic evolution and cultural evolution. === Organism === {{further|Hologenome theory of evolution}} Selection at the level of the organism can be described as [[Darwinism]], and is well understood and considered common. If a relatively faster gazelle manages to survive and reproduce more, the causation of the higher fitness of this gazelle can be fully accounted for if one looks at how individual gazelles fare under predation. The speed of the faster gazelle could be caused by a single gene, be polygenic, or be fully environmentally determined, but the unit of selection in this case is the individual since speed is a property of each individual gazelle. When speaking about individual organism evolution an [[extended phenotype]] and [[superorganism]] must be also mentioned. === Group === {{main|Group selection}} {{See also|Free-rider problem|Fisher's principle}} If a group of organisms, owing to their interactions or division of labor, provides superior fitness compared to other groups, where the fitness of the group is higher or lower than the mean fitness of the constituent individuals, group selection can be declared to occur.<ref>{{Cite web | url=https://www.britannica.com/science/group-selection |title = Group selection | biology}}</ref> Specific syndromes of selective factors can create situations in which groups are selected because they display group properties which are selected-for. Many common examples of group traits are reducible to individual traits, however. Selection of these traits is thus more simply explained as selection of individual traits. Some mosquito-transmitted rabbit viruses are only transmitted to uninfected rabbits from infected rabbits which are still alive. This creates a selective pressure on every group of viruses already infecting a rabbit not to become too virulent and kill their host rabbit before enough mosquitoes have bitten it, since otherwise all the viruses inside the dead rabbit would rot with it. And indeed in natural systems such viruses display much lower virulence levels than do mutants of the same viruses that in laboratory culture readily outcompete non-virulent variants (or than do tick-transmitted viruses since ticks do bite dead rabbits). In the previous passage, the group is assumed to have "lower virulence", i.e., "virulence" is presented as a group trait. One could argue then that the selection is in fact against individual viruses that are too virulent. In this case, however, the fitness of all viruses within a rabbit is affected by what the group does to the rabbit. Indeed, the proper, directly selected group property is that of "not killing the rabbit too early" rather than individual virulence. In situations such as these, we would expect there to be selection for cooperation amongst the viruses in a group in such a way that the group will not "kill the rabbit too early". It is of course true that any group behavior is the result of individual traits, such as individual viruses suppressing the virulence of their neighbours, but the causes of phenotypes are rarely the causes of fitness differences. === Species and higher levels === {{Main|Punctuated equilibrium}} {{See also|Speciation|Species concept|l2=Species problem|Species complex}} It remains controversial among biologists whether selection can operate at and above the level of species.<ref name="Vrba 1984">{{cite journal | last=Vrba | first=Elisabeth S. | title=What is Species Selection? | journal=Systematic Zoology | volume=33 | issue=3 | pages=318β328 | year=1984 | doi=10.2307/2413077 | jstor=2413077 }}</ref> Proponents of species selection include [[R. A. Fisher]] (1929);<ref name="Vrba 1984"/> [[Sewall Wright]] (1956);<ref name="Vrba 1984"/> [[Richard Lewontin]] (1970);<ref name="Vrba 1984"/> [[Niles Eldredge]] & [[Stephen Jay Gould]] (1972); [[Steven M. Stanley]] (1975).<ref name="Stanley 1975">{{cite journal | last=Stanley | first=SM | title=A theory of evolution above the species level. | journal=Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America | volume=72 | issue=2 | year=1975 | pmid=1054846 | pmc=432371 | pages=646β650 | doi=10.1073/pnas.72.2.646| bibcode=1975PNAS...72..646S | doi-access=free }}</ref><ref name="Vrba 1984"/> Gould proposed that there exist [[macroevolution]]ary processes which shape evolution, not driven by the [[microevolution]]ary mechanisms of the [[Neo-Darwinism|Modern Synthesis]].<ref>{{cite journal |last=Lieberman |first=Bruce S. |author2=Vrba, Elisabeth S. |title=Stephen Jay Gould on species selection: 30 years of insight |journal=Paleobiology |date=Spring 2005 |volume=31 |issue=2 Suppl |pages=113β121 |doi=10.1666/0094-8373(2005)031[0113:SJGOSS]2.0.CO;2 |s2cid=14801676 |url=http://paleo.ku.edu/geo/faculty/BSL/gouldselection.pdf |access-date=2012-07-08 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20120918210548/http://paleo.ku.edu/geo/faculty/BSL/gouldselection.pdf |archive-date=2012-09-18 |url-status=dead }}</ref> If one views species as entities that replicate (speciate) and die (go extinct) within a [[clade]], then species could be subject to selection and thus could change their occurrence over geological time, much as heritable selected-for traits change theirs over generations. For evolution to be driven by species selection, differential success must be the result of selection upon species-intrinsic properties, rather than for properties of genes, cells, individuals, or populations within species. Such properties include, for example, population structure, their propensity to speciate, extinction rates, and geological persistence. While the fossil record shows differential persistence of species, examples of species-intrinsic properties subject to natural selection have been much harder to document. One issue with selection among [[clade]]s is that they are not independent, i.e. all species are descended from the same [[last universal common ancestor]] and are thus part of the same clade.<ref name="okasha2006" /> This criticism does not apply to selection among different [[gene family|gene families]] that are not evolutionarily related, and which are [[Gene duplication|duplicated]] and lost at different rates rather than speciating and going extinct at different rates.<ref name="james2023" /> In the microbial realm, it has been interpreted that the unit of selection is a blend of ecological and functional behaviors, or [[Guild (ecology)|guilds]], beyond the species-level.<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Shapiro |first1=B. Jesse |last2=Polz |first2=Martin F. |date=May 2014 |title=Ordering microbial diversity into ecologically and genetically cohesive units |url=http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.tim.2014.02.006 |journal=Trends in Microbiology |volume=22 |issue=5 |pages=235β247 |doi=10.1016/j.tim.2014.02.006 |pmid=24630527 |issn=0966-842X|pmc=4103024 |hdl=1721.1/101684 }}</ref>
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)