Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Ramsey's theorem
(section)
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
=== Infinite graphs === A further result, also commonly called ''Ramsey's theorem'', applies to infinite graphs. In a context where finite graphs are also being discussed it is often called the "Infinite Ramsey theorem". As intuition provided by the pictorial representation of a graph is diminished when moving from finite to infinite graphs, theorems in this area are usually phrased in [[set theory|set-theoretic]] terminology.<ref>{{cite web |author=Gould |first=Martin |title=Ramsey Theory |url=http://people.maths.ox.ac.uk/~gouldm/ramsey.pdf |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20220130151921/http://people.maths.ox.ac.uk/~gouldm/ramsey.pdf |archive-date=2022-01-30 |website=[[Mathematical Institute, University of Oxford]]}}</ref> :''Theorem.'' Let <math>X</math> be some infinite set and colour the elements of <math>[X]^n</math> (the subsets of <math>X</math> of size <math>n</math>) in <math>c</math> different colours. Then there exists some infinite subset <math>M</math> of <math>X</math> such that the size <math>n</math> subsets of <math>M</math> all have the same colour. ''Proof'': The proof is by induction on {{mvar|n}}, the size of the subsets. For {{math|1=''n'' = 1}}, the statement is equivalent to saying that if you split an infinite set into a finite number of sets, then one of them is infinite. This is evident. Assuming the theorem is true for {{math|''n'' ≤ ''r''}}, we prove it for {{math|1=''n'' = ''r'' + 1}}. Given a {{mvar|c}}-colouring of the {{math|(''r'' + 1)}}-element subsets of {{mvar|X}}, let {{math|''a''{{sub|0}}}} be an element of {{mvar|X}} and let {{math|1=''Y'' = ''X '' \ {''a''{{sub|0}}<nowiki>}</nowiki>.}} We then induce a {{mvar|c}}-colouring of the {{mvar|r}}-element subsets of {{mvar|Y}}, by just adding {{math|''a''{{sub|0}}}} to each {{mvar|r}}-element subset (to get an {{math|(''r'' + 1)}}-element subset of {{mvar|X}}). By the induction hypothesis, there exists an infinite subset {{math|''Y''{{sub|1}}}} of {{mvar|Y}} such that every {{mvar|r}}-element subset of {{math|''Y''{{sub|1}}}} is coloured the same colour in the induced colouring. Thus there is an element {{math|''a''{{sub|0}}}} and an infinite subset {{math|''Y''{{sub|1}}}} such that all the {{math|(''r'' + 1)}}-element subsets of {{mvar|X}} consisting of {{math|''a''{{sub|0}}}} and {{mvar|r}} elements of {{math|''Y''{{sub|1}}}} have the same colour. By the same argument, there is an element {{math|''a''{{sub|1}}}} in {{math|''Y''{{sub|1}}}} and an infinite subset {{math|''Y''{{sub|2}}}} of {{math|''Y''{{sub|1}}}} with the same properties. Inductively, we obtain a sequence {{math|{''a''{{sub|0}}, ''a''{{sub|1}}, ''a''{{sub|2}}, …} }} such that the colour of each {{math|(''r'' + 1)}}-element subset {{math|(''a''{{sub|''i''(1)}}, ''a''{{sub|''i''(2)}}, …, ''a''{{sub|''i''(''r'' + 1)}})}} with {{math|''i''(1) < ''i''(2) < … < ''i''(''r'' + 1)}} depends only on the value of {{math|''i''(1)}}. Further, there are infinitely many values of {{math|''i''(''n'')}} such that this colour will be the same. Take these {{math|''a''{{sub|''i''(''n'')}}}}'s to get the desired monochromatic set. A stronger but unbalanced infinite form of Ramsey's theorem for graphs, the [[Erdős–Dushnik–Miller theorem]], states that every infinite graph contains either a [[countable set|countably infinite]] independent set, or an infinite clique of the same [[cardinality]] as the original graph.<ref>{{cite journal|last1=Dushnik|first1=Ben|last2=Miller|first2=E. W.|doi=10.2307/2371374|journal=American Journal of Mathematics|jstor=2371374|mr=4862|pages=600–610|title=Partially ordered sets|volume=63|year=1941|issue=3|hdl=10338.dmlcz/100377|hdl-access=free}}. See in particular Theorems 5.22 and 5.23.</ref> ==== Infinite version implies the finite ==== It is possible to deduce the finite Ramsey theorem from the infinite version by a [[proof by contradiction]]. Suppose the finite Ramsey theorem is false. Then there exist integers {{mvar|c}}, {{mvar|n}}, {{mvar|T}} such that for every integer {{mvar|k}}, there exists a {{mvar|c}}-colouring of {{math|[''k'']{{sup|(''n'')}}}} without a monochromatic set of size {{mvar|T}}. Let {{mvar|C{{sub|k}}}} denote the {{mvar|c}}-colourings of {{math|[''k'']{{sup|(''n'')}}}} without a monochromatic set of size {{mvar|T}}. For any {{mvar|k}}, the restriction of a colouring in {{math|''C''{{sub|''k''+1}}}} to {{math|[''k'']{{sup|(''n'')}}}} (by ignoring the colour of all sets containing {{math|''k'' + 1}}) is a colouring in {{mvar|C{{sub|k}}}}. Define {{tmath|C^1_k}} to be the colourings in {{mvar|C{{sub|k}}}} which are restrictions of colourings in {{math|''C''{{sub|''k''+1}}}}. Since {{math|''C''{{sub|''k''+1}}}} is not empty, neither is {{tmath|C^1_k}}. Similarly, the restriction of any colouring in {{tmath|C^1_{k+1} }} is in {{tmath|C^1_k}}, allowing one to define {{tmath|C^2_k}} as the set of all such restrictions, a non-empty set. Continuing so, define {{tmath|C^m_k}} for all integers {{mvar|m}}, {{mvar|k}}. Now, for any integer {{mvar|k}}, :<math>C_k\supseteq C^1_k\supseteq C^2_k\supseteq \cdots</math> and each set is non-empty. Furthermore, {{mvar|C{{sub|k}}}} is finite as :<math>|C_k|\le c^{\frac{k!}{n!(k-n)!}}</math> It follows that the intersection of all of these sets is non-empty, and let :<math>D_k=C_k\cap C^1_k\cap C^2_k\cap \cdots</math> Then every colouring in {{mvar|D{{sub|k}}}} is the restriction of a colouring in {{math|''D''{{sub|''k''+1}}}}. Therefore, by unrestricting a colouring in {{mvar|D{{sub|k}}}} to a colouring in {{math|''D''{{sub|''k''+1}}}}, and continuing doing so, one constructs a colouring of <math>\mathbb N^{(n)}</math> without any monochromatic set of size {{mvar|T}}. This contradicts the infinite Ramsey theorem. If a suitable topological viewpoint is taken, this argument becomes a standard [[compactness theorem|compactness argument]] showing that the infinite version of the theorem implies the finite version.<ref>{{Cite book|title=Graph Theory|last=Diestel|first=Reinhard|publisher=Springer-Verlag|year=2010|isbn=978-3-662-53621-6|edition=4|location=Heidelberg|pages=209–2010|chapter=Chapter 8, Infinite Graphs}}</ref>
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)