Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Semantics
(section)
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
== History == Semantics was established as an independent field of inquiry in the 19th century but the study of semantic phenomena began as early as the ancient period as part of philosophy and logic.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Meier-Oeser|2019|p=182}} | {{harvnb|Nerlich|1992|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=BeJBAAAAQBAJ&pg=PA2 2]}} }}</ref>{{efn|The history of semantics is different from historical semantics, which studies how the meanings of words change through time.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Geeraerts|2010|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=JC8TDAAAQBAJ&pg=PA1 1]}} | {{harvnb|Kay|2015|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=UZw7DwAAQBAJ&pg=PA1 1–2]}} }}</ref>}} In [[ancient Greece]], Plato (427–347 BCE) explored the relation between names and things in his [[Cratylus (dialogue)|dialogue ''Cratylus'']]. It considers the positions of naturalism, which holds that things have their name by nature, and conventionalism, which states that names are related to their referents by customs and conventions among language users.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Meier-Oeser|2019|pp=184–185}} | {{harvnb|Allan|2015|p=48}} | {{harvnb|Kretzmann|2006|pp=752–753}} }}</ref> The book ''[[On Interpretation]]'' by [[Aristotle]] (384–322 BCE) introduced various conceptual distinctions that greatly influenced subsequent works in semantics. He developed an early form of the semantic triangle by holding that spoken and written words evoke mental concepts, which refer to external things by resembling them. For him, mental concepts are the same for all humans, unlike the conventional words they associate with those concepts.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Meier-Oeser|2019|pp=186–187}} | {{harvnb|Kretzmann|2006|pp=755–756}} }}</ref> The [[Stoics]] incorporated many of the insights of their predecessors to develop a complex theory of language through the perspective of logic. They discerned different kinds of words by their semantic and syntactic roles, such as the contrast between names, common nouns, and verbs. They also discussed the difference between statements, commands, and prohibitions.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Meier-Oeser|2019|pp=189–191}} | {{harvnb|Kretzmann|2006|pp=757–758}} | {{harvnb|Durand|2018|p=ii}}}}</ref> [[File:Hindi Manuscript 884 Wellcome L0024558.jpg|thumb|alt=Painting of Bhartṛhari|[[Bhartṛhari]] developed and compared various semantic theories of the meaning of words.<ref>{{harvnb|Bekkum|Houben|Sluiter|Versteegh|1997|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=uU9IAAAAQBAJ&pg=PA110 110–112]}}</ref>]] In [[ancient India]], the [[Astika|orthodox school]] of [[Nyaya]] held that all names refer to real objects. It explored how words lead to an understanding of the thing meant and what consequence this relation has to the creation of knowledge.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Bekkum|Houben|Sluiter|Versteegh|1997|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=uU9IAAAAQBAJ&pg=PA102 102]}} | {{harvnb|Chakrabarti|1997|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=SbIRFAzav64C&pg=PA215 215]}} }}</ref> Philosophers of the orthodox school of [[Mīmāṃsā]] discussed the relation between the meanings of individual words and full sentences while considering which one is more basic.<ref>{{harvnb|Bekkum|Houben|Sluiter|Versteegh|1997|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=uU9IAAAAQBAJ&pg=PA75 75–76]}}</ref> The book ''[[Vākyapadīya]]'' by [[Bhartṛhari]] (4th–5th century CE) distinguished between different types of words and considered how they can carry different meanings depending on how they are used.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Aklujkar|1970|p=13}} | {{harvnb|Staal|1966|pp=304–307}} | {{harvnb|Bekkum|Houben|Sluiter|Versteegh|1997|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=uU9IAAAAQBAJ&pg=PA110 110–112]}} | {{harvnb|Cardona|2019|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=XnmVDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA303 303]}} }}</ref> In [[ancient China]], the [[Mohists]] argued that names play a key role in making distinctions to guide moral behavior.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Fraser|2023|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=x865EAAAQBAJ&pg=PA204 204–205]}} | {{harvnb|Indraccolo|2020|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=MejqDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA174 174]}} }}</ref> They inspired the [[School of Names]], which explored the relation between names and entities while examining how names are required to identify and judge entities.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Sun|2014|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=MLx_BAAAQBAJ&pg=PA23 23]}} | {{harvnb|Fraser|2020|loc=Lead Section, § 2.1 Same and Different}} }}</ref> [[File:Abelard cour Napoleon Louvre (cropped).png|thumb|left|alt=Statue of Abelard|One of [[Peter Abelard]]'s innovations was his focus on the meaning of full sentences rather than the meaning of individual words.]] In the Middle Ages, [[Augustine of Hippo]] (354–430) developed a general conception of signs as entities that stand for other entities and convey them to the intellect. He was the first to introduce the distinction between natural and linguistic signs as different types belonging to a common genus.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Meier-Oeser|2019|p=192}} | {{harvnb|Kretzmann|2006|pp=759–761}} | {{harvnb|Benin|2012|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=MdvKg89eeCkC&pg=PA94 94]}} }}</ref> [[Boethius]] (480–528) wrote a translation of and various comments on Aristotle's book ''On Interpretation'', which popularized its main ideas and inspired reflections on semantic phenomena in the [[Scholasticism|scholastic tradition]].<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Meier-Oeser|2019|pp=193–195}} | {{harvnb|Kretzmann|2006|pp=761–762}} }}</ref> An innovation in the semantics of [[Peter Abelard]] (1079–1142) was his interest in propositions or the meaning of sentences in contrast to the focus on the meaning of individual words by many of his predecessors. He further explored the nature of [[universals]], which he understood as mere semantic phenomena of [[common name]]s caused by mental abstractions that [[Nominalism|do not refer to any entities]].<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Meier-Oeser|2019|pp=197–198}} | {{harvnb|Kretzmann|2006|pp=763–764}} | {{harvnb|Provenzola|2013|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=iAvGNlIWg9IC&pg=PA22 22]}} }}</ref> In the Arabic tradition, [[Ibn Faris]] (920–1004) identified meaning with the intention of the speaker while [[Abu Mansur al-Azhari]] (895–980) held that meaning resides directly in speech and needs to be extracted through interpretation.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Bekkum|Houben|Sluiter|Versteegh|1997|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=uU9IAAAAQBAJ&pg=PA229 229]}} | {{harvnb|Leaman|2015|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=2wS2CAAAQBAJ 180]}} }}</ref> An important topic towards the end of the Middle Ages was the distinction between categorematic and [[syncategorematic term]]s. Categorematic terms have an independent meaning and refer to some part of reality, like ''horse'' and ''Socrates''. Syncategorematic terms lack independent meaning and fulfill other semantic functions, such as modifying or quantifying the meaning of other expressions, like the words ''some'', ''not'', and ''necessarily''.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Meier-Oeser|2019|pp=198–199}} | {{harvnb|Kretzmann|2006|pp=769–770}} | {{harvnb|Blackburn|2008b}} }}</ref> An early version of the causal theory of meaning was proposed by [[Roger Bacon]] (c. 1219/20 – c. 1292), who held that things get names similar to how people get names through some kind of initial baptism.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Meier-Oeser|2019|pp=200–201}} | {{harvnb|Kretzmann|2006|pp=769–770}} }}</ref> His ideas inspired the tradition of the [[speculative grammar]]ians, who proposed that there are certain universal structures found in all languages. They arrived at this conclusion by drawing an analogy between the modes of signification on the level of language, the modes of understanding on the level of mind, and the modes of being on the level of reality.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Meier-Oeser|2019|pp=201–202}} | {{harvnb|Kretzmann|2006|pp=770–771}} }}</ref> In the early modern period, [[Thomas Hobbes]] (1588–1679) distinguished between marks, which people use privately to recall their own thoughts, and signs, which are used publicly to communicate their ideas to others.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Meier-Oeser|2019|pp=205–206}} | {{harvnb|Kretzmann|2006|pp=773–774}} | {{harvnb|Martin|1953|p=210}} }}</ref> In their ''[[Port-Royal Logic]]'', [[Antoine Arnauld]] (1612–1694) and [[Pierre Nicole]] (1625–1695) developed an early precursor of the distinction between intension and extension.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Meier-Oeser|2019|pp=206–207}} | {{harvnb|Kretzmann|2006|p=777}} }}</ref> The ''[[Essay Concerning Human Understanding]]'' by John Locke (1632–1704) presented an influential version of the ideational theory of meaning, according to which words stand for ideas and help people communicate by transferring ideas from one mind to another.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Meier-Oeser|2019|pp=207–208}} | {{harvnb|Kretzmann|2006|pp=777–778}} | {{harvnb|Chapman|Routledge|2009}} }}</ref> [[Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz]] (1646–1716) understood language as the mirror of thought and tried to conceive the outlines of a [[characteristica universalis|universal formal language]] to express scientific and philosophical truths. This attempt inspired theorists [[Christian Wolff (philosopher)|Christian Wolff]] (1679–1754), [[Georg Bernhard Bilfinger]] (1693–1750), and [[Johann Heinrich Lambert]] (1728–1777) to develop the idea of a general science of sign systems.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Meier-Oeser|2019|pp=209–210}} | {{harvnb|Kretzmann|2006|pp=779–780}} }}</ref> [[Étienne Bonnot de Condillac]] (1715–1780) accepted and further developed Leibniz's idea of the linguistic nature of thought. Against Locke, he held that language is involved in the creation of ideas and is not merely a medium to communicate them.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Meier-Oeser|2019|pp=212–213}} | {{harvnb|Kretzmann|2006|pp=784–785}} }}</ref> [[File:Michel Bréal.jpg|thumb|alt=Photo of Michel Jules Alfred Bréal|[[Michel Bréal]] coined the French term ''{{lang|fr|sémantique}}'' and conceptualized the scope of this field of inquiry.]] In the 19th century, semantics emerged and solidified as an independent field of inquiry. [[Christian Karl Reisig]] (1792–1829) is sometimes credited as the father of semantics since he clarified its concept and scope while also making various contributions to its key ideas.<ref>{{harvnb|Nerlich|2019|pp=218, 221–223}}</ref> [[Michel Bréal]] (1832–1915) followed him in providing a broad conception of the field, for which he coined the French term ''{{lang|fr|sémantique}}''.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Nerlich|2019|pp=230–231}} | {{harvnb|Allan|2015|p=51}} }}</ref> [[John Stuart Mill]] (1806–1873) gave great importance to the role of names to refer to things. He distinguished between the connotation and denotation of names and held that propositions are formed by combining names.<ref>{{harvnb|Kretzmann|2006|pp=795–796}}</ref> [[Charles Sanders Peirce]] (1839–1914) conceived semiotics as a general theory of signs with several subdisciplines, which were later identified by Charles W. Morris (1901–1979) as syntactics, semantics, and pragmatics. In his pragmatist approach to semantics, Peirce held that the meaning of conceptions consists in the entirety of their practical consequences.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Burch|Parker|2024|loc=§ 4. Pragmatism, Pragmaticism, and the Scientific Method}} | {{harvnb|Kretzmann|2006|pp=797–799}} }}</ref> The philosophy of [[Gottlob Frege]] (1848–1925) contributed to semantics on many different levels. Frege first introduced the distinction between sense and reference, and his development of predicate logic and the principle of compositionality formed the foundation of many subsequent developments in formal semantics.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Kretzmann|2006|pp=787–789}} | {{harvnb|Pelletier|1994|loc=Abstract}} }}</ref> [[Edmund Husserl]] (1859–1938) explored meaning from a [[Phenomenology (philosophy)|phenomenological]] perspective by considering the mental acts that endow expressions with meaning. He held that meaning always implies reference to an object and expressions that lack a referent, like ''green is or'', are meaningless.<ref>{{harvnb|Kretzmann|2006|pp=802–803}}</ref> In the 20th century, [[Alfred Tarski]] (1901–1983) defined truth in formal languages through his [[semantic theory of truth]], which was influential in the development of truth-conditional semantics by [[Donald Davidson (philosopher)|Donald Davidson]] (1917–2003).<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Harris|2017|pp=150, 162}} | {{harvnb|Gupta|2011|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=ffYvdYfAfk8C&pg=PA236 236]}} | {{harvnb|Lepore|Ludwig|2009|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=lhJREAAAQBAJ&pg=PA1 1–2]}} }}</ref> Tarski's student [[Richard Montague]] (1930–1971) formulated a complex formal framework of the semantics of the English language, which was responsible for establishing formal semantics as a major area of research.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Harris|2017|pp=150, 162}} | {{harvnb|Chatzikyriakidis|Luo|2021|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=zt8MEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA6 6]}} }}</ref> According to [[structural semantics]],{{efn|Some theorists use the term ''structural semantics'' in a different sense to refer to phrasal semantics.<ref>{{harvnb|Rowe|Levine|2015|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=ePQ5CgAAQBAJ&pg=PA151 151]}}</ref>}} which was inspired by the [[Structuralism|structuralist philosophy]] of [[Ferdinand de Saussure]] (1857–1913), language is a complex network of structural relations and the meanings of words are not fixed individually but depend on their position within this network.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Murphy|2009|p=27}} | {{harvnb|Noth|1990|p=61}} }}</ref> The theory of [[general semantics]] was developed by [[Alfred Korzybski]] (1879–1950) as an inquiry into how language represents reality and affects human thought.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Hörmann|2013|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=euwHCAAAQBAJ&pg=PA298 298]}} | {{harvnb|Steinfatt|2009|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=S8Kf0N0XALIC&pg=PA438 438–440]}} }}</ref> The contributions of [[George Lakoff]] (1941–present) and [[Ronald Langacker]] (1942–present) provided the foundation of cognitive semantics.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Taylor|2009|p=73}} | {{harvnb|Fischer|2013|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=jdQhAAAAQBAJ&pg=PA7 7]}} }}</ref> [[Charles J. Fillmore]] (1929–2014) developed frame semantics as a major approach in this area.<ref>{{harvnb|Croft|Cruse|2004|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=I6Z9H-eRSgoC&pg=PA8 8]}}</ref> The closely related field of conceptual semantics was inaugurated by [[Ray Jackendoff]] (1945–present).<ref>{{harvnb|Östman|Fried|2005|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=e02q1C_J1OUC&pg=PA191 191–192]}}</ref>
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)