Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Set (mathematics)
(section)
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
===Infinite cardinalities=== The cardinality of an infinite set is commonly represented by a [[cardinal number]], exactly as the number of elements of a finite set is represented by a natural numbers. The definition of cardinal numbers is too technical for this article; however, many properties of cardinalities can be dealt without referring to cardinal numbers, as follows. Two sets {{tmath|S}} and {{tmath|T}} have the same cardinality if there exists a one-to-one correspondence ([[bijection]]) between them. This is denoted <math>|S|=|T|,</math> and would be an [[equivalence relation]] on sets, if a set of all sets would exist. For example, the natural numbers and the even natural numbers have the same cardinality, since multiplication by two provides such a bijection. Similarly, the [[interval (mathematics)|interval]] {{tmath|(-1, 1)}} and the set of all real numbers have the same cardinality, a bijection being provided by the function {{tmath|x\mapsto \tan(\pi x/2)}}. Having the same cardinality of a [[proper subset]] is a characteristic property of infinite sets: ''a set is infinite if and only if it has the same cardinality as one of its proper subsets.'' So, by the above example, the natural numbers form an infinite set.<ref name="Lucas1990"/> Besides equality, there is a natural inequality between cardinalities: a set {{tmath|S}} has a cardinality smaller than or equal to the cardinality of another set {{tmath|T}} if there is an [[injection (mathematics)|injection]] frome {{tmath|S}} to {{tmath|T}}. This is denoted <math>|S|\le |T|.</math> [[Schröder–Bernstein theorem]] implies that <math>|S|\le |T|</math> and <math>|T|\le |S|</math> imply <math>|S|= |T|.</math> Also, one has <math>|S|\le |T|,</math> if and only if there is a surjection from {{tmath|T}} to {{tmath|S}}. For every two sets {{tmath|S}} and {{tmath|T}}, one has either <math>|S|\le |T|</math> or <math>|T|\le |S|.</math>{{efn|This property is equivalent to the [[axiom of choice]].}} So, inequality of cardinalities is a [[total order]]. The cardinality of the set {{tmath|\N}} of the natural numbers, denoted <math>|\N|=\aleph_0,</math> is the smallest infinite cardinality. This means that if {{tmath|S}} is a set of natural numbers, then either {{tmath|S}} is finite or <math>|S|=|\N|.</math> Sets with cardinality less than or equal to <math>|\N|=\aleph_0</math> are called ''[[countable set]]s''; these are either finite sets or ''[[countably infinite set]]s'' (sets of cardinality <math>\aleph_0</math>); some authors use "countable" to mean "countably infinite". Sets with cardinality strictly greater than <math>\aleph_0</math> are called ''[[uncountable set]]s''. [[Cantor's diagonal argument]] shows that, for every set {{tmath|S}}, its power set (the set of its subsets) {{tmath|2^S}} has a greater cardinality: <math display=block>|S|<\left|2^S \right|.</math> This implies that there is no greatest cardinality.
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)