Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Arrow's impossibility theorem
(section)
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
=== Esoteric solutions === In addition to the above practical resolutions, there exist unusual (less-than-practical) situations where Arrow's requirement of IIA can be satisfied. ==== Supermajority rules ==== [[Supermajority]] rules can avoid Arrow's theorem at the cost of being poorly-decisive (i.e. frequently failing to return a result). In this case, a threshold that requires a <math>2/3</math> majority for ordering 3 outcomes, <math>3/4</math> for 4, etc. does not produce [[voting paradox]]es.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Moulin |first=HervΓ© |date=1985-02-01 |title=From social welfare ordering to acyclic aggregation of preferences |url=https://dx.doi.org/10.1016/0165-4896%2885%2990002-2 |journal=Mathematical Social Sciences |volume=9 |issue=1 |pages=1β17 |doi=10.1016/0165-4896(85)90002-2 |issn=0165-4896}}</ref> In [[Spatial model of voting|spatial (n-dimensional ideology) models of voting]], this can be relaxed to require only <math>1-e^{-1}</math> (roughly 64%) of the vote to prevent cycles, so long as the distribution of voters is well-behaved ([[quasiconcave]]).<ref name="Caplin-1988" /> These results provide some justification for the common requirement of a two-thirds majority for constitutional amendments, which is sufficient to prevent cyclic preferences in most situations.<ref name="Caplin-1988">{{Cite journal |last1=Caplin |first1=Andrew |last2=Nalebuff |first2=Barry |date=1988 |title=On 64%-Majority Rule |url=https://www.jstor.org/stable/1912699 |journal=Econometrica |volume=56 |issue=4 |pages=787β814 |doi=10.2307/1912699 |issn=0012-9682 |jstor=1912699}}</ref> ==== Infinite populations ==== [[Peter C. Fishburn|Fishburn]] shows all of Arrow's conditions can be satisfied for [[Uncountable set|uncountably infinite sets]] of voters given the [[axiom of choice]];<ref name="Fishburn197022">{{Cite journal |last=Fishburn |first=Peter Clingerman |year=1970 |title=Arrow's impossibility theorem: concise proof and infinite voters |journal=Journal of Economic Theory |volume=2 |issue=1 |pages=103β106 |doi=10.1016/0022-0531(70)90015-3}}</ref> however, Kirman and Sondermann demonstrated this requires disenfranchising [[Almost surely|almost all]] members of a society (eligible voters form a set of [[Measure (mathematics)|measure]] 0), leading them to refer to such societies as "invisible dictatorships".<ref>See Chapter 6 of {{cite book |last=Taylor |first=Alan D. |title=Social choice and the mathematics of manipulation |publisher=Cambridge University Press |year=2005 |isbn=978-0-521-00883-9 |location=New York |postscript=none}} for a concise discussion of social choice for infinite societies.</ref>
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)