Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Indeterminism
(section)
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
===Quantum mechanics=== {{main|Quantum indeterminacy}} At one time, it was assumed in the physical sciences that if the behavior observed in a system cannot be predicted, the problem is due to lack of fine-grained information, so that a sufficiently detailed investigation would eventually result in a deterministic theory ("If you knew exactly all the forces acting on the dice, you would be able to predict which number comes up"). However, the advent of [[quantum mechanics]] removed the underpinning from that approach, with the claim that (at least according to the [[Copenhagen interpretation]]) the most basic constituents of matter at times behave [[quantum indeterminism|indeterministically]]. This comes from the [[wave function collapse|collapse of the wave function]], in which the state of a system upon [[measurement problem|measurement]] cannot in general be predicted. Quantum mechanics only predicts the probabilities of possible outcomes, which are given by the [[Born rule]]. Non-deterministic behavior in wave function collapse is not only a feature of the Copenhagen interpretation, with its [[observer (quantum mechanics)|observer]]-dependence, but also of [[objective collapse theories|objective collapse]] and [[Interpretations of quantum mechanics#Comparisons|other theories]]. Opponents of quantum indeterminism suggested that determinism could be restored by formulating a new theory in which additional information, so-called [[hidden variable (physics)|hidden variables]],<ref>[https://web.archive.org/web/20110319153807/http://www.cosmosmagazine.com/features/online/4137/how-much-free-will-do-we-have Cosmos Magazine: ''How Much Free Will Do We Have'']</ref> would allow definite outcomes to be determined. For instance, in 1935, Einstein, Podolsky and Rosen wrote a paper titled ''"[[EPR paradox|Can Quantum-Mechanical Description of Physical Reality Be Considered Complete?]]"'' arguing that such a theory was in fact necessary to preserve the [[principle of locality]]. In 1964, [[John S. Bell]] was able to define [[Bell's theorem|a theoretical test]] for these local hidden variable theories, which was reformulated as a workable experimental test through the work of [[CHSH inequality|Clauser, Horne, Shimony and Holt]]. The negative result of the 1980s [[Aspect experiment|tests]] by [[Alain Aspect]] ruled such theories out, provided certain [[Loopholes in Bell test experiments|assumptions]] about the experiment hold. Thus any [[interpretation of quantum mechanics]], including deterministic reformulations, must either reject [[Principle of locality|locality]] or reject [[counterfactual definiteness]] altogether. [[David Bohm]]'s [[Bohmian quantum mechanics|theory]] is the main example of a non-local deterministic quantum theory. The [[many-worlds interpretation]] is said to be deterministic, but experimental results still cannot be predicted: experimenters do not know which 'world' they will end up in. Technically, [[counterfactual definiteness]] is lacking. A notable consequence of quantum indeterminism is the [[Heisenberg uncertainty principle]], which prevents the simultaneous accurate measurement of all a particle's properties.
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)