Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Liar paradox
(section)
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
==Possible resolutions== ===Fuzzy logic=== In [[fuzzy logic]], the truth value of a statement can be any real number between 0 and 1 both inclusive, as opposed to [[Boolean logic]], where the truth values may only be the integer values 0 or 1. In this system, the statement "This statement is false" is no longer paradoxical as it can be assigned a truth value of 0.5,<ref>{{cite journal|last1 = Hájek | first1 = P. | last2 = Paris | first2 = J. | first3 = J. | last3 = Shepherdson | title = The Liar Paradox and Fuzzy Logic | journal = The Journal of Symbolic Logic | volume = 61 | number = 1 | pages = 339–346 | date = Mar 2000 | doi=10.2307/2586541 | jstor = 2586541 | s2cid = 6865763 }}</ref><ref>{{cite journal | last1 = Kehagias | first1 = Athanasios | last2 = Vezerides | first2 = K. | title = Computation of fuzzy truth values for the liar and related self-referential systems | url = http://users.auth.gr/~kehagiat/Papers/journal/2007MVLSC.pdf | journal = Journal of Multiple-Valued Logic and Soft Computing | volume = 12 | number = 5–6 | pages = 539–559 | date = Aug 2006 | access-date = 2021-02-17 | archive-date = 2021-07-08 | archive-url = https://web.archive.org/web/20210708230916/http://users.auth.gr/~kehagiat/Papers/journal/2007MVLSC.pdf | url-status = live }}</ref> making it precisely half true and half false. A simplified explanation is shown below. Let the truth value of the statement "This statement is false" be denoted by <math display>x</math>. The statement becomes : <math display="block"> x = NOT(x) </math> by generalizing the NOT operator to the equivalent [[Zadeh operator]] from [[fuzzy logic]], the statement becomes : <math display="block"> x = 1 - x </math> from which it follows that : <math display="block"> x = 0.5 </math> ===Alfred Tarski=== [[Alfred Tarski]] diagnosed the paradox as arising only in languages that are "semantically closed", by which he meant a language in which it is possible for one sentence to predicate truth (or falsehood) of another sentence in the same language (or even of itself). To avoid self-contradiction, it is necessary when discussing truth values to envision levels of languages, each of which can predicate truth (or falsehood) only of languages at a lower level. So, when one sentence refers to the truth-value of another, it is semantically higher. The sentence referred to is part of the "object language", while the referring sentence is considered to be a part of a "meta-language" with respect to the object language. It is legitimate for sentences in "languages" higher on the semantic hierarchy to refer to sentences lower in the "language" hierarchy, but not the other way around. This prevents a system from becoming self-referential. However, this system is incomplete. One would like to be able to make statements such as "For every statement in level ''α'' of the hierarchy, there is a statement at level ''α''+1 which asserts that the first statement is false." This is a true, meaningful statement about the hierarchy that Tarski defines, but it refers to statements at every level of the hierarchy, so it must be above every level of the hierarchy, and is therefore not possible within the hierarchy (although bounded versions of the sentence are possible).<ref name=Kripke.1975>{{cite conference |last1=Kripke |first1=Saul |author-link=Saul Kripke |date=1975-11-06 |title=Outline of a theory of truth |conference=Seventy-Second Annual Meeting American Philosophical Association, Eastern Division |publisher=Journal of Philosophy |volume=72 |number=19 |pages=690–716 |doi=10.2307/2024634 |jstor=2024634 }}</ref><ref name=PlatoProject.LiarParadox.TarskiHier>{{cite web |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/liar-paradox/#TarsHierLang |title=Liar Paradox: Section 4.3.1 Tarski's hierarchy of languages |access-date=2021-01-16 |date=2016-12-12 |orig-date=January 20, 2011 |first1=Jc |last1=Beall |first2=Michael |last2=Glanzberg |first3=David |last3=Ripley |archive-date=2021-01-12 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210112011051/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/liar-paradox/#TarsHierLang |url-status=live }}</ref> [[Saul Kripke]] is credited with identifying this incompleteness in Tarski's hierarchy in his highly cited paper "Outline of a theory of truth,"<ref name=PlatoProject.LiarParadox.TarskiHier/> and it is recognized as a general problem in hierarchical languages.<ref name=PlatoProject.LiarParadox.TarskiHier/><ref>{{cite book |first1=Michael |last1=Glanzberg |chapter=Complexity and Hierarchy in Truth Predicates|publisher=Springer|location= Dordrecht |title=Unifying the Philosophy of Truth|series= Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science |volume=36 |date=2015-06-17 |pages=211–243 |doi=10.1007/978-94-017-9673-6_10 |isbn=978-94-017-9672-9 }}</ref> ===Arthur Prior=== [[Arthur Prior]] asserts that there is nothing paradoxical about the liar paradox. His claim (which he attributes to [[Charles Sanders Peirce]] and [[John Buridan]]) is that [[Deflationary theory of truth#Redundancy theory|every statement includes an implicit assertion of its own truth]].<ref>{{cite book |last= Kirkham |first= Richard |author-link= Richard Kirkham |date= 1992 |title= [[Theories of Truth|Theories of Truth: A Critical Introduction]] |publisher= MIT Press |at= section 9.6 "A. N. Prior's Solution" |isbn= 0-262-61108-2 }}</ref> Thus, for example, the statement "It is true that two plus two equals four" contains no more information than the statement "two plus two equals four", because the phrase "it is true that..." is always implicitly there. And in the self-referential spirit of the Liar Paradox, the phrase "it is true that..." is equivalent to "this whole statement is true and ...". Thus the following two statements are equivalent: {{block indent |This statement is false.}} {{block indent |This statement is true and this statement is false.}} The latter is a simple contradiction of the form "A and not A", and hence is false. Therefore, there is no paradox, because the claim that this two-conjunct Liar is false does not lead to a contradiction. Eugene Mills presents a similar answer. <ref>{{cite journal | last1 = Mills | first1 = Eugene | year = 1998 | title = A simple solution to the Liar | journal = Philosophical Studies | volume = 89 | issue = 2/3| pages = 197–212 | doi = 10.1023/a:1004232928938 | s2cid = 169981769 }}</ref> ===Saul Kripke=== [[Saul Kripke]] argued that whether a sentence is paradoxical or not can depend upon contingent facts.<ref name=Kripke.1975/>{{rp|6}} If the only thing Smith says about Jones is {{block indent |A majority of what Jones says about me is false.}} and Jones says only these three things about Smith: {{block indent |Smith is a big spender.}} {{block indent |Smith is soft on crime.}} {{block indent |Everything Smith says about me is true.}} If Smith really is a big spender but is ''not'' soft on crime, then both Smith's remark about Jones and Jones's last remark about Smith are paradoxical. Kripke proposes a solution in the following manner. If a statement's truth value is ultimately tied up in some evaluable fact about the world, that statement is "grounded". If not, that statement is "ungrounded". Ungrounded statements do not have a truth value. Liar statements and liar-like statements are ungrounded, and therefore have no truth value. ===Jon Barwise and John Etchemendy=== [[Jon Barwise]] and [[John Etchemendy]] propose that the liar sentence (which they interpret as synonymous with the Strengthened Liar) is ambiguous. They base this conclusion on a distinction they make between a "denial" and a "negation". If the liar means, "It is not the case that this statement is true", then it is denying itself. If it means, "This statement is not true", then it is negating itself. They go on to argue, based on [[situation semantics]], that the "denial liar" can be true without contradiction while the "negation liar" can be false without contradiction. Their 1987 book makes heavy use of [[non-well-founded set theory]].<ref name="Barwise1989"/> ===Dialetheism=== [[Graham Priest]] and other logicians, including J. C. Beall and Bradley Armour-Garb, have proposed that the liar sentence should be considered to be both true and false, a point of view known as [[dialetheism]]. Dialetheism is the view that there are true contradictions. Dialetheism raises its own problems. Chief among these is that since dialetheism recognizes the liar paradox, an intrinsic contradiction, as being true, it must discard the long-recognized [[principle of explosion]], which asserts that any proposition can be deduced from a contradiction, unless the dialetheist is willing to accept trivialism – the view that ''all'' propositions are true. Since trivialism is an intuitively false view, dialetheists nearly always reject the explosion principle. Logics that reject it are called ''[[paraconsistent]]''. ===Non-cognitivism=== [[Andrew David Irvine|Andrew Irvine]] has argued in favour of a non-cognitivist solution to the paradox, suggesting that some apparently well-formed sentences will turn out to be neither true nor false and that "formal criteria alone will inevitably prove insufficient" for resolving the paradox.<ref name="Andrew Irvine 1992"/> ===Bhartrhari's perspectivism=== The Indian grammarian-philosopher [[Bhartrhari]] (late fifth century AD) dealt with paradoxes such as the liar in a section of one of the chapters of his magnum opus the Vākyapadīya.{{Citation needed|date=May 2022}} Bhartrhari's solution fits into his general approach to language, thought and reality, which has been characterized by some as "relativistic", "non-committal" or "perspectivistic".<ref>Jan E. M. Houben, "Bhartrhari's Perspectivism (1)" in ''Beyond Orientalism'' ed. by Eli Franco and Karin Preisendanz, Amsterdam – Atlanta: Rodopi, 1997; [[Madeleine Biardeau]] recognized that Bhartrhari "wants to rise at once above all controversies by showing the conditions of possibility of any system of interpretation, rather than to prove the truth of a certain particular system" (Théorie de la connaissance et philosophie de la parole dans le brahmanisme classique, Paris – La Haye: Mouton, 1964, p. 263)</ref> With regard to the liar paradox (''sarvam mithyā bravīmi'' "everything I am saying is false") Bhartrhari identifies a hidden parameter that can change unproblematic situations in daily communication into a stubborn paradox. Bhartrhari's solution can be understood in terms of the solution proposed in 1992 by Julian Roberts: "Paradoxes consume themselves. But we can keep apart the warring sides of the contradiction by the simple expedient of temporal contextualisation: what is 'true' with respect to one point in time need not be so in another ... The overall force of the 'Austinian' argument is not merely that 'things change', but that rationality is essentially temporal in that we need time in order to reconcile and manage what would otherwise be mutually destructive states."<ref>Roberts, Julian. 1992. ''The Logic of Reflection. German Philosophy in the Twentieth Century''. New Haven and London: Yale University Press. p. 43.</ref> According to Robert's suggestion, it is the factor "time" which allows us to reconcile the separated "parts of the world" that play a crucial role in the solution of Barwise and Etchemendy.<ref name="Barwise1989"/>{{rp|188}} The capacity of time to prevent a direct confrontation of the two "parts of the world" is here external to the "liar". In the light of Bhartrhari's analysis, however, the extension in time that separates two perspectives on the world or two "parts of the world" – the part before and the part after the function accomplishes its task – is inherent in any "function": also the function to signify which underlies each statement, including the "liar".<ref name=JEMH2001/>{{Unclear inline|date=May 2022}} The unsolvable paradox – a situation in which we have either contradiction (''virodha'') or infinite regress (''anavasthā'') – arises, in case of the liar and other paradoxes such as the unsignifiability paradox ([[Bhartrhari's paradox]]), when abstraction is made from this function (''vyāpāra'') and its extension in time, by accepting a simultaneous, opposite function (''apara vyāpāra'') undoing the previous one.
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)