Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Mathematical proof
(section)
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
=={{Anchor|Types of proof}}Methods of proof== ===Direct proof=== {{Main|Direct proof}} In direct proof, the conclusion is established by logically combining the axioms, definitions, and earlier theorems.<ref>Cupillari, p. 20.</ref> For example, direct proof can be used to prove that the sum of two [[parity (mathematics)|even]] [[integer]]s is always even: :Consider two even integers ''x'' and ''y''. Since they are even, they can be written as ''x'' = 2''a'' and ''y'' = 2''b'', respectively, for some integers ''a'' and ''b''. Then the sum is ''x'' + ''y'' = 2''a'' + 2''b'' = 2(''a''+''b''). Therefore ''x''+''y'' has 2 as a [[divisor|factor]] and, by definition, is even. Hence, the sum of any two even integers is even. This proof uses the definition of even integers, the integer properties of [[Closure (mathematics)|closure]] under addition and multiplication, and the [[distributive property]]. ===Proof by mathematical induction=== {{Main|Mathematical induction}} Despite its name, mathematical induction is a method of [[Deductive reasoning|deduction]], not a form of [[inductive reasoning]]. In proof by mathematical induction, a single "base case" is proved, and an "induction rule" is proved that establishes that any arbitrary case [[Material conditional|implies]] the next case. Since in principle the induction rule can be applied repeatedly (starting from the proved base case), it follows that all (usually [[Infinite set|infinitely]] many) cases are provable.<ref>Cupillari, p. 46.</ref> This avoids having to prove each case individually. A variant of mathematical induction is [[proof by infinite descent]], which can be used, for example, to prove the [[Square root of 2#Proofs of irrationality|irrationality of the square root of two]]. A common application of proof by mathematical induction is to prove that a property known to hold for one number holds for all [[natural number]]s:<ref>[http://zimmer.csufresno.edu/~larryc/proofs/proofs.mathinduction.html Examples of simple proofs by mathematical induction for all natural numbers]</ref> Let {{math|1='''N''' = {1, 2, 3, 4, ...}}} be the set of natural numbers, and let {{math|''P''(''n'')}} be a mathematical statement involving the natural number {{math|''n''}} belonging to {{math|'''N'''}} such that * '''(i)''' {{math|''P''(1)}} is true, i.e., {{math|''P''(''n'')}} is true for {{math|1=''n'' = 1}}. * '''(ii)''' {{math|''P''(''n''+1)}} is true whenever {{math|''P''(''n'')}} is true, i.e., {{math|''P''(''n'')}} is true implies that {{math|''P''(''n''+1)}} is true. * '''Then {{math|''P''(''n'')}} is true for all natural numbers {{math|''n''}}.''' For example, we can prove by induction that all positive integers of the form {{math|2''n'' − 1}} are [[parity (mathematics)|odd]]. Let {{math|''P''(''n'')}} represent "{{math|2''n'' − 1}} is odd": :'''(i)''' For {{math|1=''n'' = 1}}, {{math|1=2''n'' − 1 = 2(1) − 1 = 1}}, and {{math|1}} is odd, since it leaves a remainder of {{math|1}} when divided by {{math|2}}. Thus {{math|''P''(1)}} is true. :'''(ii)''' For any {{math|''n''}}, if {{math|2''n'' − 1}} is odd ({{math|''P''(''n'')}}), then {{math|(2''n'' − 1) + 2}} must also be odd, because adding {{math|2}} to an odd number results in an odd number. But {{math|1=(2''n'' − 1) + 2 = 2''n'' + 1 = 2(''n''+1) − 1}}, so {{math|1=2(''n''+1) − 1}} is odd ({{math|''P''(''n''+1)}}). So {{math|''P''(''n'')}} implies {{math|''P''(''n''+1)}}. :'''Thus''' {{math|2''n'' − 1}} is odd, for all positive integers {{math|''n''}}. The shorter phrase "proof by induction" is often used instead of "proof by mathematical induction".<ref>[http://www.warwick.ac.uk/AEAhelp/glossary/glossaryParser.php?glossaryFile=Proof%20by%20induction.htm Proof by induction] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20120218033011/http://www.warwick.ac.uk/AEAhelp/glossary/glossaryParser.php?glossaryFile=Proof%20by%20induction.htm |date=February 18, 2012 }}, University of Warwick Glossary of Mathematical Terminology</ref> ===Proof by contraposition=== {{Main|Contraposition}} [[Proof by contrapositive|Proof by contraposition]] [[Rule of inference|infers]] the statement "if ''p'' then ''q''" by establishing the [[logically equivalent]] [[contrapositive|contrapositive statement]]: "if ''not q'' then ''not p''". For example, contraposition can be used to establish that, given an integer <math>x</math>, if <math> x^2 </math> is even, then <math>x</math> is even: : Suppose <math>x</math> is not even. Then <math>x</math> is odd. The product of two odd numbers is odd, hence <math> x^2 = x\cdot x </math> is odd. Thus <math> x^2 </math> is not even. Thus, if <math> x^2 </math> ''is'' even, the supposition must be false, so <math> x </math> has to be even. ===Proof by contradiction=== {{Main|Proof by contradiction}} In proof by contradiction, also known by the Latin phrase ''[[reductio ad absurdum]]'' (by reduction to the absurd), it is shown that if some statement is assumed true, a [[contradiction|logical contradiction]] occurs, hence the statement must be false. A famous example involves the proof that <math>\sqrt{2}</math> is an [[irrational number]]: :Suppose that <math>\sqrt{2}</math> were a rational number. Then it could be written in lowest terms as <math>\sqrt{2} = {a\over b}</math> where ''a'' and ''b'' are non-zero integers with [[coprime|no common factor]]. Thus, <math>b\sqrt{2} = a</math>. Squaring both sides yields 2''b''<sup>2</sup> = ''a''<sup>2</sup>. Since the expression on the left is an integer multiple of 2, the right expression is by definition divisible by 2. That is, ''a''<sup>2</sup> is even, which implies that ''a'' must also be even, as seen in the proposition above (in [[#Proof by contraposition]]). So we can write ''a'' = 2''c'', where ''c'' is also an integer. Substitution into the original equation yields 2''b''<sup>2</sup> = (2''c'')<sup>2</sup> = 4''c''<sup>2</sup>. Dividing both sides by 2 yields ''b''<sup>2</sup> = 2''c''<sup>2</sup>. But then, by the same argument as before, 2 divides ''b''<sup>2</sup>, so ''b'' must be even. However, if ''a'' and ''b'' are both even, they have 2 as a common factor. This contradicts our previous statement that ''a'' and ''b'' have no common factor, so we must conclude that <math>\sqrt{2}</math> is an irrational number. To paraphrase: if one could write <math>\sqrt{2}</math> as a [[fraction]], this fraction could never be written in lowest terms, since 2 could always be factored from numerator and denominator. ===Proof by construction=== {{Main|Proof by construction}} Proof by construction, or proof by example, is the construction of a concrete example with a property to show that something having that property exists. [[Joseph Liouville]], for instance, proved the existence of [[transcendental number]]s by constructing an [[Liouville number|explicit example]]. It can also be used to construct a [[counterexample]] to disprove a proposition that all elements have a certain property. ===Proof by exhaustion=== {{Main|Proof by exhaustion}} In proof by exhaustion, the conclusion is established by dividing it into a finite number of cases and proving each one separately. The number of cases sometimes can become very large. For example, the first proof of the [[four color theorem]] was a proof by exhaustion with 1,936 cases. This proof was controversial because the majority of the cases were checked by a computer program, not by hand.<ref>See [[Four color theorem#Simplification and verification]].</ref> === Closed chain inference === {{Main|Closed chain inference}} A closed chain inference shows that a collection of statements are pairwise equivalent. In order to prove that the statements <math>\varphi_1,\ldots,\varphi_n</math> are each pairwise equivalent, proofs are given for the implications <math>\varphi_1\Rightarrow\varphi_2</math>, <math>\varphi_2\Rightarrow\varphi_3</math>, <math>\dots</math>, <math>\varphi_{n-1}\Rightarrow\varphi_n</math> and <math>\varphi_{n}\Rightarrow\varphi_1</math>.<ref>{{Cite book |last1=Plaue |first1=Matthias |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=-WCHDwAAQBAJ |title=Mathematik für das Bachelorstudium I: Grundlagen und Grundzüge der linearen Algebra und Analysis |last2=Scherfner |first2=Mike |date=2019-02-11 |publisher=Springer-Verlag |isbn=978-3-662-58352-4 |pages=26 |language=de |trans-title=Mathematics for the Bachelor's degree I: Fundamentals and basics of linear algebra and analysis}}</ref><ref>{{Cite book |last1=Struckmann |first1=Werner |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=1epNDQAAQBAJ |title=Mathematik für Informatiker: Grundlagen und Anwendungen |last2=Wätjen |first2=Dietmar |date=2016-10-20 |publisher=Springer-Verlag |isbn=978-3-662-49870-5 |pages=28 |language=de |trans-title=Mathematics for Computer Scientists: Fundamentals and Applications}}</ref> The pairwise equivalence of the statements then results from the [[Transitive relation|transitivity]] of the [[material conditional]]. ===Probabilistic proof=== {{Main|Probabilistic method}} A probabilistic proof is one in which an example is shown to exist, with certainty, by using methods of [[probability theory]]. Probabilistic proof, like proof by construction, is one of many ways to prove [[existence theorem]]s. In the probabilistic method, one seeks an object having a given property, starting with a large set of candidates. One assigns a certain probability for each candidate to be chosen, and then proves that there is a non-zero probability that a chosen candidate will have the desired property. This does not specify which candidates have the property, but the probability could not be positive without at least one. A probabilistic proof is not to be confused with an argument that a theorem is 'probably' true, a 'plausibility argument'. The work toward the [[Collatz conjecture]] shows how far plausibility is from genuine proof, as does the disproof of the [[Mertens conjecture]]. While most mathematicians do not think that probabilistic evidence for the properties of a given object counts as a genuine mathematical proof, a few mathematicians and philosophers have argued that at least some types of probabilistic evidence (such as Rabin's [[probabilistic algorithm]] for [[primality test|testing primality]]) are as good as genuine mathematical proofs.<ref>Davis, Philip J. (1972), "Fidelity in Mathematical Discourse: Is One and One Really Two?" ''American Mathematical Monthly'' 79:252–63.</ref><ref>Fallis, Don (1997), "The Epistemic Status of Probabilistic Proof." ''Journal of Philosophy'' 94:165–86.</ref> ===Combinatorial proof=== {{Main|Combinatorial proof}} A combinatorial proof establishes the equivalence of different expressions by showing that they count the same object in different ways. Often a [[bijection]] between two [[set (mathematics)|sets]] is used to show that the expressions for their two sizes are equal. Alternatively, a [[double counting (proof technique)|double counting argument]] provides two different expressions for the size of a single set, again showing that the two expressions are equal. ===Nonconstructive proof=== {{Main|Nonconstructive proof}} A nonconstructive proof establishes that a [[mathematical object]] with a certain property exists—without explaining how such an object can be found. Often, this takes the form of a proof by contradiction in which the nonexistence of the object is proved to be impossible. In contrast, a constructive proof establishes that a particular object exists by providing a method of finding it. The following famous example of a nonconstructive proof shows that there exist two [[irrational number]]s ''a'' and ''b'' such that <math>a^b</math> is a [[rational number]]. This proof uses that <math>\sqrt{2}</math> is irrational (an easy proof is known since [[Euclid]]), but not that <math>\sqrt{2}^{\sqrt{2}}</math> is irrational (this is true, but the proof is not elementary). :Either <math>\sqrt{2}^{\sqrt{2}}</math> is a rational number and we are done (take <math>a=b=\sqrt{2}</math>), or <math>\sqrt{2}^{\sqrt{2}}</math> is irrational so we can write <math>a=\sqrt{2}^{\sqrt{2}}</math> and <math>b=\sqrt{2}</math>. This then gives <math>\left (\sqrt{2}^{\sqrt{2}}\right )^{\sqrt{2}}=\sqrt{2}^{2}=2</math>, which is thus a rational number of the form <math>a^b.</math> ===Statistical proofs in pure mathematics=== {{Main| Statistical proof}} The expression "statistical proof" may be used technically or colloquially in areas of [[pure mathematics]], such as involving [[cryptography]], [[chaotic series]], and [[probabilistic|probabilistic number theory]] or [[analytic number theory]].<ref>"in number theory and commutative algebra... in particular the statistical proof of the lemma." [https://www.jstor.org/pss/2686395]</ref><ref>"Whether constant π (i.e., pi) is normal is a confusing problem without any strict theoretical demonstration except for some ''statistical'' proof"" (Derogatory use.)[https://doi.org/10.1007%2F978-3-540-74282-1_78]</ref><ref>"these observations suggest a statistical proof of Goldbach's conjecture with very quickly vanishing probability of failure for large E" [http://people.web.psi.ch/gassmann/eneseminare/abstracts/Goldbach1.pdf]</ref> It is less commonly used to refer to a mathematical proof in the branch of mathematics known as [[mathematical statistics]]. See also the "[[#Colloquial use, Statistical proof using data|Statistical proof using data]]" section below. ===Computer-assisted proofs=== {{Main|Computer-assisted proof }} Until the twentieth century it was assumed that any proof could, in principle, be checked by a competent mathematician to confirm its validity.<ref name="Krantz">[http://www.math.wustl.edu/~sk/eolss.pdf The History and Concept of Mathematical Proof], Steven G. Krantz. 1. February 5, 2007</ref> However, computers are now used both to prove theorems and to carry out calculations that are too long for any human or team of humans to check; the first proof of the [[four color theorem]] is an example of a computer-assisted proof. Some mathematicians are concerned that the possibility of an error in a computer program or a run-time error in its calculations calls the validity of such computer-assisted proofs into question. In practice, the chances of an error invalidating a computer-assisted proof can be reduced by incorporating redundancy and self-checks into calculations, and by developing multiple independent approaches and programs. Errors can never be completely ruled out in case of verification of a proof by humans either, especially if the proof contains natural language and requires deep mathematical insight to uncover the potential hidden assumptions and fallacies involved.
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)