Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Continuous function
(section)
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
==Related notions== If <math>f : S \to Y</math> is a continuous function from some subset <math>S</math> of a topological space <math>X</math> then a {{em|{{visible anchor|continuous extension|Continuous extension}}}} of <math>f</math> to <math>X</math> is any continuous function <math>F : X \to Y</math> such that <math>F(s) = f(s)</math> for every <math>s \in S,</math> which is a condition that often written as <math>f = F\big\vert_S.</math> In words, it is any continuous function <math>F : X \to Y</math> that [[Restriction of a function|restricts]] to <math>f</math> on <math>S.</math> This notion is used, for example, in the [[Tietze extension theorem]] and the [[Hahn–Banach theorem]]. If <math>f : S \to Y</math> is not continuous, then it could not possibly have a continuous extension. If <math>Y</math> is a [[Hausdorff space]] and <math>S</math> is a [[Dense set|dense subset]] of <math>X</math> then a continuous extension of <math>f : S \to Y</math> to <math>X,</math> if one exists, will be unique. The [[Blumberg theorem]] states that if <math>f : \R \to \R</math> is an arbitrary function then there exists a dense subset <math>D</math> of <math>\R</math> such that the restriction <math>f\big\vert_D : D \to \R</math> is continuous; in other words, every function <math>\R \to \R</math> can be restricted to some dense subset on which it is continuous. Various other mathematical domains use the concept of continuity in different but related meanings. For example, in [[order theory]], an order-preserving function <math>f : X \to Y</math> between particular types of [[partially ordered set]]s <math>X</math> and <math>Y</math> is continuous if for each [[Directed set|directed subset]] <math>A</math> of <math>X,</math> we have <math>\sup f(A) = f(\sup A).</math> Here <math>\,\sup\,</math> is the [[supremum]] with respect to the orderings in <math>X</math> and <math>Y,</math> respectively. This notion of continuity is the same as topological continuity when the partially ordered sets are given the [[Scott topology]].<ref>{{cite book |last=Goubault-Larrecq |first=Jean |title=Non-Hausdorff Topology and Domain Theory: Selected Topics in Point-Set Topology |publisher=[[Cambridge University Press]]|year=2013 |isbn=978-1107034136}}</ref><ref>{{cite book |last1=Gierz |first1=G. |last2=Hofmann |first2=K. H. |last3=Keimel |first3=K. |last4=Lawson |first4=J. D. |last5=Mislove |first5=M. W. |last6=Scott |first6=D. S. |title=Continuous Lattices and Domains |volume=93 |series=Encyclopedia of Mathematics and its Applications |publisher=Cambridge University Press |year=2003 |isbn=0521803381 |url-access=registration |url=https://archive.org/details/continuouslattic0000unse}}</ref> In [[category theory]], a [[functor]] <math display="block">F : \mathcal C \to \mathcal D</math> between two [[Category (mathematics)|categories]] is called {{em|[[Continuous functor|continuous]]}} if it commutes with small [[Limit (category theory)|limits]]. That is to say, <math display="block">\varprojlim_{i \in I} F(C_i) \cong F \left(\varprojlim_{i \in I} C_i \right)</math> for any small (that is, indexed by a set <math>I,</math> as opposed to a [[class (mathematics)|class]]) [[Diagram (category theory)|diagram]] of [[Object (category theory)|objects]] in <math>\mathcal C</math>. A {{em|[[continuity space]]}} is a generalization of metric spaces and posets,<ref>{{cite journal | title = Quantales and continuity spaces | citeseerx=10.1.1.48.851 | first = R. C. | last =Flagg | journal = Algebra Universalis | year = 1997 | volume=37 | issue=3 | pages=257–276 | doi=10.1007/s000120050018 | s2cid=17603865 }}</ref><ref>{{cite journal | title = All topologies come from generalized metrics | first = R. | last = Kopperman | journal = American Mathematical Monthly | year = 1988 |volume=95 |issue=2 |pages=89–97 |doi=10.2307/2323060 | jstor = 2323060 }}</ref> which uses the concept of [[quantale]]s, and that can be used to unify the notions of metric spaces and [[Domain theory|domain]]s.<ref>{{cite journal | title = Continuity spaces: Reconciling domains and metric spaces | first1 = B. | last1 = Flagg | first2 = R. | last2 = Kopperman | journal = Theoretical Computer Science |volume=177 |issue=1 |pages=111–138 |doi=10.1016/S0304-3975(97)00236-3 | year = 1997 | doi-access = free }}</ref> In [[measure theory]], a function <math>f : E \to \mathbb{R}^k</math> defined on a [[Lebesgue measurable set]] <math>E \subseteq \mathbb{R}^n</math> is called [[approximately continuous]] at a point <math>x_0 \in E</math> if the [[approximate limit]] of <math>f</math> at <math>x_0</math> exists and equals <math>f(x_0)</math>. This generalizes the notion of continuity by replacing the ordinary limit with the [[approximate limit]]. A fundamental result known as the [[Stepanov-Denjoy theorem]] states that a function is [[measurable function|measurable]] if and only if it is approximately continuous [[almost everywhere]].<ref>{{cite book |last=Federer |first=H. |title=Geometric measure theory |publisher=Springer-Verlag |series=Die Grundlehren der mathematischen Wissenschaften |volume=153 |location=New York |year=1969 |isbn= |pages=}}</ref>
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)