Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Form of the Good
(section)
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
===Other criticisms=== Plato's Form of the Good is often criticized as too general.<ref name=BAR>{{cite book|last=Reeve|first=C.D.C.|title=Blindness and reorientation : problems in Plato's Republic|date=2013|publisher=Oxford University Press|location=Oxford|isbn=978-0-19-993443-0|pages=165, 166|edition=1.}}</ref> Plato's Form of the Good does not define things in the physical world that are good, and therefore lacks connectedness to reality.<ref>{{cite book|last=Herman|first=Arthur|title=The cave and the light : Plato versus Aristotle, and the struggle for the soul of Western civilization|date=2013|publisher=Bantam Books|location=New York|isbn=978-0-553-80730-1|page=46|edition=First}}</ref> Because Plato's Form of the Good lacks instruction, or ways for the individual to be good, Plato's Form of the Good is not applicable to human ethics since there is no defined method for which goodness can be pursued. Through Socrates in ''The Republic'', Plato acknowledges the Form of the Good as an elusive concept and proposes that the Form of the Good be accepted as a hypothesis, rather than criticized for its weaknesses. According to Socrates in ''The Republic'', the only alternative to accepting a hypothesis is to refute all the objections against it, which is counterproductive in the process of contemplation.<ref name=BAR /> Aristotle along with other scholars sees the Form of the Good as synonymous with the idea of One.<ref name=Rev>{{cite journal|last=Jordan|first=R.W.|title=Platos Idee des Guten by Rafael Ferber Review|journal=The Classical Review|date=1986|volume=36|pages=65β67|jstor=3064234|doi=10.1017/s0009840x00105001|s2cid=170977273 }}</ref> Plato claims that Good is the highest Form, and that all objects aspire to be good.<ref>{{cite web|last=Banach|first=David|title=Plato's Theory of Forms|url=http://www.anselm.edu/homepage/dbanach/platform.htm|access-date=2 May 2014|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20140803230257/http://www.anselm.edu/homepage/dbanach/platform.htm|archive-date=3 August 2014|url-status=dead}}</ref> Since Plato does not define good things, interpreting Plato's Form of the Good through the idea of One allows scholars to explain how Plato's Form of the Good relates to the physical world. According to this philosophy, in order for an object to belong to the Form of the Good, it must be One and have the proper harmony, uniformity, and order to be in its proper form.<ref name=Rev /> Philosopher Rafael Ferber dismissed Aristotle's view that the 'Good' is 'One' and wrote that the Form of the Good is self-contradictory. Ferber claimed that Plato's Form of the Good could be simultaneously defined and unknown, and be in a state of both "being" and "not being".<ref name=Rev /> Plato's Forms are also critiqued for being treated as the reason for all things, as opposed to being an essence in itself. Some scholars also believe that Plato intended the Form to be the essence of which things come into existence. These different interpretations of Plato's intention for the Form may be attributed to the idea that Plato did not have a systematic definition of the Form itself.<ref name=plat />
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)