Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Philosophical methodology
(section)
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
=== Geometrical method === The geometrical method came to particular prominence through rationalists like [[Baruch Spinoza]]. It starts from a small set of [[self-evident]] [[axioms]] together with relevant definitions and tries to deduce a great variety of theorems from this basis, thereby mirroring the methods found in [[geometry]].<ref>{{cite web |last1=Goldenbaum |first1=Ursula |title=Geometrical Method |url=https://iep.utm.edu/geo-meth/ |website=Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |access-date=17 February 2022}}</ref><ref>{{cite book |last1=Nadler |first1=Steven |title=Spinoza's 'Ethics': An Introduction |date=2006 |publisher=Cambridge University Press |isbn=978-0-521-83620-3 |pages=35–51 |url=https://www.cambridge.org/core/books/abs/spinozas-ethics/geometric-method/08550AF622C78ACC388069710D37036E |chapter=The geometric method}}</ref> Historically, it can be understood as a response to methodological skepticism: it consists in trying to find a foundation of certain knowledge and then expanding this foundation through [[deductive inferences]]. The theorems arrived at this way may be challenged in two ways. On the one hand, they may be derived from axioms that are not as self-evident as their defenders proclaim and thereby fail to inherit the status of absolute certainty.<ref name="DalyHandbook"/> For example, many philosophers have rejected the claim of self-evidence concerning one of [[René Descartes]]'s first principles stating that "he can know that whatever he perceives clearly and distinctly is true only if he first knows that God exists and is not a deceiver".<ref name="DalyHandbook"/><ref>{{cite web |last1=Hatfield |first1=Gary |title=René Descartes: 3.5 God and error |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/descartes/#GodErr |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=27 February 2022 |date=2018}}</ref> Another example is the causal axiom of Spinoza's system that "the knowledge of an effect depends on and involves knowledge of its cause", which has been criticized in various ways.<ref>{{cite book |last1=Doppelt |first1=Torin |title=Spinoza's Causal Axiom: A Defense |date=2010 |url=https://qspace.library.queensu.ca/bitstream/handle/1974/6052/Doppelt_Torin_201009_MA.pdf |chapter=3: The Truth About 1A4}}</ref> In this sense, philosophical systems built using the geometrical method are open to criticisms that reject their basic axioms. A different form of objection holds that the inference from the axioms to the theorems may be faulty, for example, because it does not follow a [[rule of inference]] or because it includes implicitly assumed premises that are not themselves self-evident.<ref name="DalyHandbook"/>
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)