Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Transfer principle
(section)
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
== Generalizations of the concept of number == Historically, the concept of [[number]] has been repeatedly generalized. The addition of [[0 (number)|0]] to the natural numbers <math>\mathbb{N}</math> was a major intellectual accomplishment in its time. The addition of negative integers to form <math>\mathbb{Z}</math> already constituted a departure from the realm of immediate experience to the realm of mathematical models. The further extension, the rational numbers <math>\mathbb{Q}</math>, is more familiar to a layperson than their completion <math>\mathbb{R}</math>, partly because the reals do not correspond to any physical reality (in the sense of measurement and computation) different from that represented by <math>\mathbb{Q}</math>. Thus, the notion of an irrational number is meaningless to even the most powerful floating-point computer. The necessity for such an extension stems not from physical observation but rather from the internal requirements of mathematical coherence. The infinitesimals entered mathematical discourse at a time when such a notion was required by mathematical developments at the time, namely the emergence of what became known as the [[calculus|infinitesimal calculus]]. As already mentioned above, the mathematical justification for this latest extension was delayed by three centuries. [[Howard Jerome Keisler|Keisler]] wrote: :"In discussing the real line we remarked that we have no way of knowing what a line in physical space is really like. It might be like the hyperreal line, the real line, or neither. However, in applications of the calculus, it is helpful to imagine a line in physical space as a hyperreal line." The [[consistency|self-consistent]] development of the hyperreals turned out to be possible if every true [[first-order logic]] statement that uses basic arithmetic (the [[natural number]]s, plus, times, comparison) and quantifies only over the real numbers was assumed to be true in a reinterpreted form if we presume that it quantifies over hyperreal numbers. For example, we can state that for every real number there is another number greater than it: : <math> \forall x \in \mathbb{R} \quad \exists y \in\mathbb{R}\quad x < y. </math> The same will then also hold for hyperreals: : <math> \forall x \in {}^\star\mathbb{R} \quad \exists y \in {}^\star\mathbb{R}\quad x < y. </math> Another example is the statement that if you add 1 to a number you get a bigger number: : <math> \forall x \in \mathbb{R} \quad x < x+1 </math> which will also hold for hyperreals: : <math> \forall x \in {}^\star\mathbb{R} \quad x < x+1. </math> The correct general statement that formulates these equivalences is called the transfer principle. Note that, in many formulas in analysis, quantification is over higher-order objects such as functions and sets, which makes the transfer principle somewhat more subtle than the above examples suggest.
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)