Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Contradiction
(section)
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
=== The notion of contradiction in an axiomatic system and a proof of its consistency === In general, a [[consistency proof]] requires the following two things: # An [[axiomatic system]] # A demonstration that it is ''not'' the case that both the formula ''p'' and its negation ''~p'' can be derived in the system. But by whatever method one goes about it, all consistency proofs would ''seem'' to necessitate the primitive notion of ''contradiction.'' Moreover, it ''seems'' as if this notion would simultaneously have to be "outside" the formal system in the definition of tautology. When [[Emil Post]], in his 1921 "Introduction to a General Theory of Elementary Propositions", extended his proof of the consistency of the [[propositional calculus]] (i.e. the logic) beyond that of ''[[Principia Mathematica]]'' (PM), he observed that with respect to a ''generalized'' set of postulates (i.e. axioms), he would no longer be able to automatically invoke the notion of "contradiction"{{mdash}}such a notion might not be contained in the postulates: {{quote|The prime requisite of a set of postulates is that it be consistent. Since the ordinary notion of consistency involves that of contradiction, which again involves negation, and since this function does not appear in general as a primitive in [the ''generalized'' set of postulates] a new definition must be given.<ref>Post 1921 "Introduction to a General Theory of Elementary Propositions" in van Heijenoort 1967:272.</ref>}} Post's solution to the problem is described in the demonstration "An Example of a Successful Absolute Proof of Consistency", offered by [[Ernest Nagel]] and [[James R. Newman]] in their 1958 ''[[Gödel]]'s Proof''. They too observed a problem with respect to the notion of "contradiction" with its usual "truth values" of "truth" and "falsity". They observed that: {{quote|The property of being a tautology has been defined in notions of truth and falsity. Yet these notions obviously involve a reference to something ''outside'' the formula calculus. Therefore, the procedure mentioned in the text in effect offers an ''interpretation'' of the calculus, by supplying a model for the system. This being so, the authors have not done what they promised, namely, "'''to define a property of formulas in terms of purely structural features of the formulas themselves'''". [Indeed] ... proofs of consistency which are based on models, and which argue from the truth of axioms to their consistency, merely shift the problem.<ref>boldface italics added, Nagel and Newman:109-110.</ref>}} Given some "primitive formulas" such as PM's primitives S<sub>1</sub> V S<sub>2</sub> [inclusive OR] and ~S (negation), one is forced to define the axioms in terms of these primitive notions. In a thorough manner, Post demonstrates in PM, and defines (as do Nagel and Newman, see below) that the property of ''tautologous'' – as yet to be defined – is "inherited": if one begins with a set of tautologous axioms (postulates) and a [[deduction system]] that contains [[substitution (logic)|substitution]] and [[modus ponens]], then a ''consistent'' system will yield only tautologous formulas. On the topic of the definition of ''tautologous'', Nagel and Newman create two [[mutually exclusive]] and [[Collectively exhaustive events|exhaustive]] classes K<sub>1</sub> and K<sub>2</sub>, into which fall (the outcome of) the axioms when their variables (e.g. S<sub>1</sub> and S<sub>2</sub> are assigned from these classes). This also applies to the primitive formulas. For example: "A formula having the form S<sub>1</sub> V S<sub>2</sub> is placed into class K<sub>2</sub>, if both S<sub>1</sub> and S<sub>2</sub> are in K<sub>2</sub>; otherwise it is placed in K<sub>1</sub>", and "A formula having the form ~S is placed in K<sub>2</sub>, if S is in K<sub>1</sub>; otherwise it is placed in K<sub>1</sub>".<ref>Nagel and Newman:110-111</ref> Hence Nagel and Newman can now define the notion of ''[[tautology (logic)|tautologous]]'': "a formula is a tautology if and only if it falls in the class K<sub>1</sub>, no matter in which of the two classes its elements are placed".<ref>Nagel and Newman:111</ref> This way, the property of "being tautologous" is described—without reference to a model or an interpretation. {{quote|For example, given a formula such as ~S<sub>1</sub> V S<sub>2</sub> and an assignment of K<sub>1</sub> to S<sub>1</sub> and K<sub>2</sub> to S<sub>2</sub> one can evaluate the formula and place its outcome in one or the other of the classes. The assignment of K<sub>1</sub> to S<sub>1</sub> places ~S<sub>1</sub> in K<sub>2</sub>, and now we can see that our assignment causes the formula to fall into class K<sub>2</sub>. Thus by definition our formula is not a tautology.}} Post observed that, if the system were inconsistent, a deduction in it (that is, the last formula in a sequence of formulas derived from the tautologies) could ultimately yield S itself. As an assignment to variable S can come from either class K<sub>1</sub> or K<sub>2</sub>, the deduction violates the inheritance characteristic of tautology (i.e., the derivation must yield an evaluation of a formula that will fall into class K<sub>1</sub>). From this, Post was able to derive the following definition of inconsistency—''without the use of the notion of contradiction'': {{quote|Definition. ''A system will be said to be inconsistent if it yields the assertion of the unmodified variable p [S in the Newman and Nagel examples].''}} In other words, the notion of "contradiction" can be dispensed when constructing a proof of consistency; what replaces it is the notion of "mutually exclusive and exhaustive" classes. An axiomatic system need not include the notion of "contradiction".<ref name=jstor1921 >Emil L. Post [https://www.jstor.org/stable/2370324 (1921) Introduction to a General Theory of Elementary Propositions] ''American Journal of Mathematics'' '''43''' (3):163—185 (1921) The Johns Hopkins University Press </ref>{{rp|177}}
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)