Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Ultrafilter
(section)
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
==Applications== Ultrafilters on [[power set]]s are useful in [[topology]], especially in relation to [[Compact space|compact]] [[Hausdorff space|Hausdorff]] spaces, and in [[model theory]] in the construction of [[Ultraproduct|ultraproducts and ultrapowers]]. Every ultrafilter on a compact Hausdorff space converges to exactly one point. Likewise, ultrafilters on Boolean algebras play a central role in [[Stone's representation theorem for Boolean algebras|Stone's representation theorem]]. In [[set theory]] ultrafilters are used to show that the [[axiom of constructibility]] is incompatible with the existence of a [[measurable cardinal]] {{mvar|κ}}. This is proved by taking the ultrapower of the set theoretical universe modulo a {{mvar|κ}}-complete, non-principal ultrafilter.<ref> Kanamori, The Higher infinite, p. 49.</ref> The set <math>G</math> of all ultrafilters of a poset <math display="inline">P</math> can be topologized in a natural way, that is in fact closely related to the above-mentioned representation theorem. For any element <math>x</math> of <math display="inline">P</math>, let <math>D_x = \left\{ U \in G : x \in U \right\}.</math> This is most useful when <math display="inline">P</math> is again a Boolean algebra, since in this situation the set of all <math>D_x</math> is a base for a compact Hausdorff topology on <math>G</math>. Especially, when considering the ultrafilters on a powerset <math>{\mathcal P}(S)</math>, the resulting [[topological space]] is the [[Stone–Čech compactification]] of a [[discrete space]] of cardinality <math>| S |.</math> The [[ultraproduct]] construction in [[model theory]] uses ultrafilters to produce a new model starting from a sequence of <math>X</math>-indexed models; for example, the [[compactness theorem]] can be proved this way. In the special case of ultrapowers, one gets [[elementary extension]]s of structures. For example, in [[nonstandard analysis]], the [[hyperreal number]]s can be constructed as an ultraproduct of the [[real numbers]], extending the [[domain of discourse]] from real numbers to sequences of real numbers. This sequence space is regarded as a [[superset]] of the reals by identifying each real with the corresponding constant sequence. To extend the familiar functions and relations (e.g., + and <) from the reals to the hyperreals, the natural idea is to define them pointwise. But this would lose important logical properties of the reals; for example, pointwise < is not a total ordering. So instead the functions and relations are defined "[[Ultraproduct#Definition|pointwise modulo]]" <math>U</math>, where <math>U</math> is an ultrafilter on the [[index set]] of the sequences; by [[Łoś' theorem]], this preserves all properties of the reals that can be stated in [[first-order logic]]. If <math>U</math> is nonprincipal, then the extension thereby obtained is nontrivial. In [[geometric group theory]], non-principal ultrafilters are used to define the [[Ultralimit#Asymptotic cones|asymptotic cone]] of a group. This construction yields a rigorous way to consider {{em|looking at the group from infinity}}, that is the large scale geometry of the group. Asymptotic cones are particular examples of [[ultralimit]]s of [[metric space]]s. [[Gödel's ontological proof]] of God's existence uses as an axiom that the set of all "positive properties" is an ultrafilter. In [[social choice theory]], non-principal ultrafilters are used to define a rule (called a ''social welfare function'') for aggregating the preferences of ''infinitely'' many individuals. Contrary to [[Arrow's impossibility theorem]] for ''finitely'' many individuals, such a rule satisfies the conditions (properties) that Arrow proposes (for example, Kirman and Sondermann, 1972).<ref>{{Cite journal|last1 = Kirman|first1 = A.|last2 = Sondermann|first2 = D.|title = Arrow's theorem, many agents, and invisible dictators|journal = Journal of Economic Theory|volume = 5|issue = 2|pages = 267–277|year = 1972|doi = 10.1016/0022-0531(72)90106-8}}</ref> Mihara (1997,<ref name=mihara97>{{Cite journal|last1 = Mihara|first1 = H. R.|title = Arrow's Theorem and Turing computability|journal = Economic Theory|volume = 10|issue = 2|pages = 257–276|year = 1997|postscript = Reprinted in K. V. Velupillai, S. Zambelli, and S. Kinsella, ed., Computable Economics, International Library of Critical Writings in Economics, Edward Elgar, 2011.|doi = 10.1007/s001990050157|url = https://econwpa.ub.uni-muenchen.de/econ-wp/pe/papers/9408/9408001.pdf|citeseerx = 10.1.1.200.520|s2cid = 15398169 }}</ref> 1999)<ref name=mihara99>{{Cite journal|last1 = Mihara|first1 = H. R.|title = Arrow's theorem, countably many agents, and more visible invisible dictators|journal = [[Journal of Mathematical Economics]]|volume = 32|issue = 3|pages = 267–277|year = 1999|doi = 10.1016/S0304-4068(98)00061-5|url= http://econpapers.repec.org/paper/wpawuwppe/9705001.htm|citeseerx = 10.1.1.199.1970}}</ref> shows, however, such rules are practically of limited interest to social scientists, since they are non-algorithmic or non-computable.
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)