Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Church–Turing thesis
(section)
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
==Success of the thesis== Other formalisms (besides recursion, the [[Lambda calculus|λ-calculus]], and the [[Turing machine]]) have been proposed for describing effective calculability/computability. Kleene (1952) adds to the list the functions "''reckonable'' in the system S<sub>1</sub>" of [[Kurt Gödel]] 1936, and [[Emil Post]]'s (1943, 1946) "''canonical'' [also called ''normal''] ''systems''".<ref>Kleene 1952:320</ref> In the 1950s [[Hao Wang (academic)|Hao Wang]] and [[Martin Davis (mathematician)|Martin Davis]] greatly simplified the one-tape Turing-machine model (see [[Post–Turing machine]]). [[Marvin Minsky]] expanded the model to two or more tapes and greatly simplified the tapes into "up-down counters", which Melzak and [[Joachim Lambek|Lambek]] further evolved into what is now known as the [[counter machine]] model. In the late 1960s and early 1970s researchers expanded the counter machine model into the [[register machine]], a close cousin to the modern notion of the [[computer]]. Other models include [[combinatory logic]] and [[Markov algorithm]]s. Gurevich adds the [[pointer machine]] model of Kolmogorov and Uspensky (1953, 1958): "... they just wanted to ... convince themselves that there is no way to extend the notion of computable function."<ref>Gurevich 1988:2</ref> All these contributions involve proofs that the models are computationally equivalent to the Turing machine; such models are said to be [[Turing complete]]. Because all these different attempts at formalizing the concept of "effective calculability/computability" have yielded equivalent results, it is now generally assumed that the Church–Turing thesis is correct. In fact, Gödel (1936) proposed something stronger than this; he observed that there was something "absolute" about the concept of "reckonable in S<sub>1</sub>": {{quote|It may also be shown that a function which is computable ['reckonable'] in one of the systems S<sub>i</sub>, or even in a system of transfinite type, is already computable [reckonable] in S<sub>1</sub>. Thus the concept 'computable' ['reckonable'] is in a certain definite sense 'absolute', while practically all other familiar metamathematical concepts (e.g. provable, definable, etc.) depend quite essentially on the system to which they are defined ...<ref>Translation of Gödel (1936) by Davis in ''The Undecidable'' p. 83, differing in the use of the word 'reckonable' in the translation in Kleene (1952) p. 321</ref>}}<!-- In the early twentieth century, mathematicians often used the informal phrase ''effectively computable'', so it was important to find a good formalization of the concept. Modern mathematicians instead use the well-defined term ''Turing computable'' (or ''computable'' for short). Since the undefined terminology has faded from use, the question of how to define it is now less important.-->
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)