Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Fact–value distinction
(section)
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
==Criticisms== Virtually all modern philosophers affirm ''some'' sort of fact–value distinction, insofar as they distinguish between science and "valued" disciplines such as [[ethics]], [[aesthetics]], or the fine [[arts]]. However, philosophers such as [[Hilary Putnam]] argue that the distinction between fact and value is not as absolute as Hume envisioned.<ref>{{Cite web |url=http://www.reasonpapers.com/pdf/28/rp_28_9.pdf |title=The Collapse of the Fact/Value Dichotomy and Other Essays, Cambridge, MA : Harvard University Press, 2002 |author=Putnam, Hilary |publisher=Reasonpapers.com |access-date=2013-10-03}}</ref> Philosophical [[pragmatists]], for instance, believe that true propositions are those that are ''useful'' or ''effective'' in predicting future (empirical) states of affairs.<ref>{{Cite web |url=http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#PeiTruRea |title=Pragmatism (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy) |publisher=Plato.stanford.edu |date=2008-08-16 |access-date=2013-10-03}}</ref> Far from being value-free, the pragmatists' conception of truth or facts directly relates to an end (namely, empirical predictability) that human beings regard as ''normatively'' desirable. Other thinkers, such as [[Norwood Russell Hanson|N. Hanson]] among others, talk of [[theory-ladenness]], and reject an absolutist fact–value distinction by contending that our senses are imbued with prior conceptualizations, making it impossible to have any observation that is totally value-free, which is how Hume and the later [[Positivism|positivists]] conceived of facts. ===Functionalist counterexamples=== Several counterexamples have been offered by philosophers claiming to show that there are cases when an evaluative statement does indeed logically follow from a factual statement. [[Arthur Prior|A. N. Prior]] argues, from the statement "He is a sea captain," that it logically follows, "He ought to do what a sea captain ought to do."{{sfn|MacIntyre|2007|p=[https://archive.org/details/aftervirtuestudy00alas/page/57 57]}} [[Alasdair MacIntyre]] argues, from the statement "This watch is grossly inaccurate and irregular in time-keeping and too heavy to carry about comfortably," that the evaluative conclusion validly follows, "This is a bad watch."{{sfn|MacIntyre|2007|p=[https://archive.org/details/aftervirtuestudy00alas/page/57 57–58]}} [[John Searle]] argues, from the statement "Jones promised to pay Smith five dollars," that it logically follows that "Jones ought to pay Smith five dollars", such that the act of promising by definition places the promiser under obligation.<ref>{{Cite book |last=MacNiven |first=Don |url=https://archive.org/details/creativemorality0000macn/page/40/mode/2up |title=Creative Morality |date=1993 |publisher=[[Routledge]] |isbn=978-0415000307 |pages=41–42}}</ref> ===Moral realism=== [[Philippa Foot]] adopts a [[Moral realism|moral realist]] position, criticizing the idea that when evaluation is superposed on fact there has been a "committal in a new dimension".<ref>Philippa Foot, “Moral Beliefs,” ''Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society'', vol. 59 (1958), pp. 83–104.</ref> She introduces, by analogy, the practical implications of using the word "injury". Not just anything counts as an injury. There must be some impairment. When we suppose a man wants the things the injury prevents him from obtaining, haven’t we fallen into the old naturalist fallacy? {{quote|It may seem that the only way to make a necessary connection between 'injury' and the things that are to be avoided, is to say that it is only used in an 'action-guiding sense' when applied to something the speaker intends to avoid. But we should look carefully at the crucial move in that argument, and query the suggestion that someone might happen not to want anything for which he would need the use of hands or eyes. Hands and eyes, like ears and legs, play a part in so many operations that a man could only be said not to need them if he had no wants at all.<ref>Foot 1958, p. 96.</ref>}} Foot argues that the virtues, like hands and eyes in the analogy, play so large a part in so many operations that it is implausible to suppose that a committal in a non-naturalist dimension is necessary to demonstrate their goodness. {{quote|Philosophers who have supposed that actual action was required if 'good' were to be used in a sincere evaluation have got into difficulties over weakness of will, and they should surely agree that enough has been done if we can show that any man has reason to aim at virtue and avoid vice. But is this impossibly difficult if we consider the kinds of things that count as virtue and vice? Consider, for instance, the cardinal virtues, prudence, temperance, courage and justice. Obviously any man needs prudence, but does he not also need to resist the temptation of pleasure when there is harm involved? And how could it be argued that he would never need to face what was fearful for the sake of some good? It is not obvious what someone would mean if he said that temperance or courage were not good qualities, and this not because of the 'praising' sense of these words, but because of the things that courage and temperance are.<ref>Foot 1958, p. 97.</ref>}} === Of Weber<!--For [[Post-truth]] page, where this paragraph is pasted from.--> === Philosopher [[Leo Strauss]] criticizes Weber for attempting to isolate reason completely from opinion. Strauss acknowledges the [[Is–ought problem|philosophical trouble of deriving "ought" from "is"]], but argues that what Weber has done in his framing of this puzzle is in fact deny altogether that the "ought" is within reach of human reason.<ref name='leo'>{{Cite book |last=Strauss, Leo |title=Natural right and history |date=2008 |publisher=University of Chicago Press |isbn=978-0226776941 |oclc=551845170}}</ref>{{rp|66}} Strauss worries that if Weber is right, we are left with a world in which the knowable truth is a truth that cannot be evaluated according to ethical standards. This conflict between ethics and politics would mean that there can be no grounding for any valuation of the good, and without reference to values, facts lose their meaning.<ref name='leo'></ref>{{rp|72}}
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)