Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Mu'tazilism
(section)
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
==Beliefs== {{Aqidah|Other}} ===The Five Principles=== According to a "leading Mu'tazilite authority" of the end of the ninth century (al-Khayyat),<ref name=Fakhry-46a>{{cite book| last=Fakhry |first=Majid |edition=second |title=A History of Islamic Philosophy |publisher=Columbia University Press |location=New York |year=1983|page=46|quote=Thus according to a leading Mu'talite authority of the end of the ninth century, five basic tenets make up the strict Mu'tazilite creed: monotheism, justice and unity, the inevitability of the threats and promises of God, the intermediary position, the injunction of right and the prohibition of wrong.}}</ref> and "clearly enunciated for the first time by [[Abu al-Hudhayl al-'Allaf|Abu al-Hudhayl]]",<ref name="robinson2"/> five basic tenets make up the Mu'tazilite creed: #monotheism,<ref name=khayyat-93/> #justice and unity,<ref name=khayyat-93/> #the inevitability of the threats and promises of God (or "the warning and the promise"),<ref name=khayyat-93/> #the intermediary position (i.e. Muslims who die without repentance after committing a grave sin are neither ''mu'mineen'' (believers), nor ''kuffar'' (non-believers), but in an intermediate position known as ''fasiq''),<ref name=khayyat-93/> #the injunction of right, and the prohibition of wrong.<ref name=khayyat-93>Al-Khayyat, A.H., ''Kitab al-Intisar'', Beirut, 1957, p.93</ref> ====1. Monotheism==== All Muslim schools of theology faced the dilemma of affirming [[Transcendence (religion)|divine transcendence]] and [[Conceptions of God|divine attributes]], without falling into [[anthropomorphism]] on the one hand or emptying scriptural references to those attributes of all concrete meaning.{{sfn|Jackson|2005}} The doctrine of Tawhīd, in the words of the prominent Mu'tazili scholar Chief Justice [[Qadi Abd al-Jabbar]] (died 415 AH/1025 AD)<ref>{{Cite web |url=https://irl.umsl.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1006&context=philosophy-faculty |title=Archived copy |access-date=2021-03-25 |archive-date=2021-08-17 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210817155204/https://irl.umsl.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1006&context=philosophy-faculty |url-status=live }}</ref> is: <blockquote> the knowledge that God, being unique, has attributes that no creature shares with him. This is explained by the fact that you know that the world has a creator who created it and that: he existed eternally in the past and he cannot perish while we exist after being non-existent and we can perish. And you know that he was and is eternally all-powerful and that impotence is not possible for him. And you know that he is [[omniscient]] of the past and present and that ignorance is not possible for him. And you know that he knows everything that was, everything that is, and how things that are not would be if they were. And you know that he is eternally in the past and future living, and that calamities and pain are not possible for him. And you know that he sees visible things, and perceives perceptibles, and that he does not have need of sense organs. And you know that he is eternally past and in future sufficient and it is not possible for him to be in need. And you know that he is not like physical bodies, and that it is not possible for him to get up or down, move about, change, be composite, have a form, limbs and body members. And you know that he is not like the accidents of motion, rest, color, food or smells. And you know that he is One throughout eternity and there is no second beside him, and that everything other than he is contingent, made, dependent, structured, and governed by someone/thing else. Thus, if you know all of that you know the oneness of God.{{sfn|Martin|1997|p=92}}</blockquote> ====2. Divine justice==== Facing the [[Problem of evil|problem of existence of evil]] in the world, the Mu'tazilis pointed at the free will of human beings, so that evil was defined as something that stems from the errors in human acts. God does nothing ultimately evil, and he demands not from any human to perform any evil act. If man's evil acts had been from the will of God, then punishment would have been meaningless, as man performed the will of God no matter what he did. Mu'tazilis did not deny the existence of suffering that goes beyond human abuse and misuse of their free will granted to them by God. In order to explain this type of "apparent" evil, Mu'tazilis relied on the Islamic doctrine of ''taklif'': "God does not order/give the soul of any of his creation, that which is beyond its capacity." [Qur'an 2:286]. In conclusion, it comprised life is an ultimate "fair test" of coherent and rational choices, having a supremely just accountability in one's current state, as well as the hereafter.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Madelung |first=Wilferd |date=1992 |title=Studies in Medieval Muslim Thought and History |url=https://doi.org/10.4324/9781003221883 |journal=New Editions from 2016 on by Routledge, Oxon and New York |publisher=Ashgate Publishing |doi=10.4324/9781003221883|isbn=978-1-003-22188-3 }}</ref> Humans are required to have belief, ''[[Iman (concept)|iman]]'', secure faith and conviction in and about God, and do good works, ''amal saleh'', to have ''iman'' reflected in their moral choices, deeds, and relationship with God, fellow humans, and all of the creation in this world. If everyone is healthy and wealthy, then there will be no meaning for the obligations imposed on humans to, for example, be generous, help the needy, and have compassion for the deprived and trivialized. The inequalities in human fortunes and the calamities that befell them are, thus, an integral part of the test of life. Everyone is being tested. The powerful, the rich, and the healthy are required to use all their powers and privileges to help those who suffer and to alleviate their suffering. In the [[Qiyamah]] (Judgment Day), they will be questioned about their response to Divine blessings and bounties they enjoyed in their lives. The less fortunate are required to patiently persevere and are promised a compensation for their suffering that, as the [[Qur'an]] puts it in 39:10, and as translated by [[Muhammad Asad]], is "beyond all reckoning".<ref>{{Cite web|date=2010-09-26|title=Message Of Quran By Muhammad Asad 039 – WikiMir|url=http://www.wikimir.com/message-of-quran-by-muhammad-asad-039|access-date=2021-02-04|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20100926172903/http://www.wikimir.com/message-of-quran-by-muhammad-asad-039|archive-date=2010-09-26}}</ref> The test of life is specifically for adults in full possession of their mental faculties. Children may suffer, and are observed to suffer, given the nature of life but they are believed to be completely free from sin and liability. Divine justice is affirmed through the theory of compensation. All sufferers will be compensated. This includes non-believers and, more importantly, children, who are destined to go to [[Paradise]].<ref>{{Cite web |last=Akyol |first=Mustafa |date=October 27, 2022 |title=An Early Islamic Debate on Faith and Reason Is Worth Examining |url=https://www.cato.org/commentary/early-islamic-debate-faith-reason-worth-examining |access-date=December 15, 2024 |website=www.cato.org}}</ref><ref>{{Cite journal |last=Aytekin |first=Arif |date=2022-06-30 |title=The Question Regarding the Children of Nonbelievers in Islam |url=https://dergipark.org.tr/en/pub/atebe/issue/71028/1081309 |journal=ATEBE |language=en |issue=7 |pages=129–147 |issn=2757-5616}}</ref> The doctrine of '[[Adl]] in the words of ʿAbd al-Jabbar:{{sfn|Martin|1997|page=58}} It is the knowledge that God is removed from all that is morally wrong (''qabih'') and that all his acts are morally good (''[[hasana]]''). This is explained by the fact that you know that all human acts of injustice (''[[zulm]]''), transgression (''jawr''), and the like cannot be of his creation (''min khalqihi''). Whoever attributes that to him has ascribed to him injustice and insolence (''safah'') and thus strays from the doctrine of justice. And you know that God does not impose faith upon the unbeliever without giving him the power (''al-qudra'') for it, nor does he impose upon a human what he is unable to do, but he only gives to the unbeliever to choose unbelief on his own part, not on the part of God. And you know that God does not will, desire or want disobedience. Rather, he loathes and despises it and only wills obedience, which he wants and chooses and loves. And you know that he does not punish the children of polytheists (''al-[[mushrik]]in'') in Hellfire because of their fathers' sin, for he has said: "Each soul earns but its own due" (Qur'an 6:164); and he does not punish anyone for someone else's sin because that would be morally wrong (''qabih''), and God is far removed from such. And you know that he does not transgress his rule ([[hukm]]) and that he only causes sickness and illness in order to turn them to advantage. Whoever says otherwise has allowed that God is iniquitous and has imputed insolence to him. And you know that, for their sakes, he does the best for all of his creatures, upon whom he imposes moral and religious obligations (''yukallifuhum''), and that He has indicated to them what he has imposed upon them and clarified the path of truth so that we could pursue it, and he has clarified the path of falsehood (''tariq l-batil'') so that we could avoid it. So, whoever perishes does so only after all this has been made clear. And you know that every benefit we have is from God; as he has said: "And you have no good thing that is not from Allah" (Qur'an 16:53); it either comes to us from him or from elsewhere. Thus, when you know all of this you become knowledgeable about justice from God.{{sfn|Martin|1997|page=93}} ====3. The Promise and the Threat [''al-wa'd wa l-wa'id'']==== This comprised questions of the Last day, or in Arabic, the [[Qiyamah]] ([[Judgment Day|Day of Judgment]]). According to 'Abd al-Jabbar,{{sfn|Martin|1997|page=65-6}} The doctrine of irreversible Divine promises and warnings, is fashioned out the Islamic philosophy of human existence. Humans, (or ''insan'' in Arabic) are created with an innate need in their essence to submit themselves to something. Also, it is seen as an innate need of all humans to pursue an inner peace and contentment within the struggles of an imperfect world. Knowledge of God, truth, and choices, in relation to one's innate need of submission is seen in Islam as the promise and recompense of God (''al-thawab'') to those who follow. His warning is looked at as a conscious decision by a human submitting themselves, and choosing a varying principle which he had given a clear warning to. He will not go back on his word, nor can he act contrary to his promise and warning, nor lie in what he reports, in contrast to what the Postponers ([[Murjites]]) hold.<ref name=":2" /><ref name=":1" /> ====4. The Intermediate Position [''Al-Manzilah bayn al-manzilatayn'']==== That is, Muslims who commit grave sins and die without repentance are not considered as mu’minīn (believers), nor are they considered kafirs (non-believers), but in an intermediate position between the two, (''fasiq''). The reason behind this is that a mu’min is, by definition, a person who has faith and conviction in and about God, and who has their faith reflected in their deeds and moral choices. Any shortcoming on any of these two fronts makes one, by definition, not a mu’min. On the other hand, one does not become a ''kafir'' (i.e. rejecter; non-believer), for this entails, inter alia, denying the Creator—something not necessarily done by a committer of a grave sin. The fate of those who commit grave sins and die without repentance is Hell. Hell is not considered a monolithic state of affairs but as encompassing many degrees to accommodate the wide spectrum of human deeds and choices, and the lack of comprehension associated to The Ultimate Judge (one of the other names in Islam of God.) Consequently, those in the intermediate position, though in Hell, would have a lesser punishment because of their belief and other good deeds. Mu'tazilites adopted this position as a middle ground between [[Kharijites]] and [[Murjites]]. In the words of ʿAbd al-Jabbar, the doctrine of the intermediate position is{{sfn|Martin|1997|page=82, 106}} the knowledge that whoever murders, or commits [[zina]], or commits serious sins is a grave sinner (''fasiq'') and not a believer, nor is his case the same that of believers with respect to praise and attributing greatness, since he is to be cursed and disregarded. Nonetheless, he is not an unbeliever who cannot be buried in our Muslim cemetery, or be prayed for, or marry a Muslim. Rather, he has an intermediate position, in contrast to the Seceders ([[Kharijites]]) who say that he is an unbeliever, or the [[Murjites]] who say that he is a believer.<ref>{{Cite web |last=Mutahhari |first=Murtadha |date=2013-03-12 |title=Mu'tazilah {{!}} An Introduction to Ilm al-Kalam |url=https://www.al-islam.org/al-tawhid/vol3-no2/introduction-ilm-al-kalam-murtadha-mutahhari/mutazilah |access-date=2024-12-15 |website=al-Islam.org |language=en}}</ref> ====5. The enjoining of right and prohibiting of wrong==== These two tenets, like the "intermediate position", follow logically (according to scholar Majid Fakhry) from the basic Mu'tazilite concepts of divine unity, justice and free will, of which they are the logical conclusion.<ref name=Fakhry-46a/> Even though they are accepted [[Enjoining good and forbidding wrong|by most Muslims]], Mu'tazilites give them a specific interpretation in the sense that, even though God enjoins what is right and prohibits what is wrong, the use of reason allows a Muslim in most cases to identify for himself what is right and what is wrong, even without the help of revelation. Only for some acts is the revelation necessary to determine whether a certain act is right or wrong.<ref>{{Cite web |title=Ash'ariyya and Mu'tazila - Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy |url=https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/ash-ariyya-and-mu-tazila/v-1# |archive-url=http://web.archive.org/web/20240803001911/https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/ash-ariyya-and-mu-tazila/v-1 |archive-date=2024-08-03 |access-date=2024-12-15 |website=www.rep.routledge.com |language=en}}</ref> ===Theory of interpretation=== Mu'tazila relied on a synthesis between [[reason]] and [[revelation]]. That is, their [[rationalism]] operated in the service of scripture and [[Islamic theology|Islamic theological]] framework. They, as the majority of Muslim jurist-theologians, validated [[allegorical]] readings of [[Religious text|scripture]] whenever necessary. Justice [[Abd al-Jabbar ibn Ahmad|ʿAbd al-Jabbar]] (935–1025) said in his ''Sharh al-Usul al-Khamsa'' (The Explication of the Five Principles):<ref name=":2">{{Cite book |last=al-Asadābādī |first=ʻAbd al-Jabbār ibn Aḥmad |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=_PilAQAACAAJ |title=Sharḥ al-Uṣūl al-Khamsah |date= 1965|publisher=Maktabat Wahbah |language=ar}}</ref> {{Quote|إن الكلام متى لم يمكن حمله على ظاهره و حقيقته، و هناك مجازان أحدهما أقرب و الآخر أبعد، فإن الواجب حمله على المجاز الأقرب دون الأبعد، لأن المجاز الأبعد من الأقرب كالمجاز مع الحقيقة، و كما لا يجوز فى خطاب الله تعالى أن يحمل على المجاز مع إمكان حمله على الحقيقة، فكذلك لا يحمل على المجاز الأبعد و هناك ما هو أقرب منه (When a text cannot be interpreted according to its truth and apparent meaning, and when (in this case) two metaphoric interpretations are possible, one being proximal and the other being distal; then, in this case, we are obligated to interpret the text according to the proximal metaphoric interpretation and not the distal, for (the relationship between) the distal to the proximal is like unto (the relationship between) the metaphor to the truth, and in the same way that it is not permissible, when dealing with the word of God, to prefer a metaphoric interpretation when a discernment of the truth is possible, it is also not permissible to prefer the distal interpretation over the proximal interpretation) }} The [[Hermeneutics|hermeneutic]] methodology proceeds as follows: if the literal meaning of an [[ayah]] (verse) is consistent with the rest of scripture, the main themes of the [[Qur'an]], the basic tenets of the [[Islamic creed]], and the well-known facts, then [[Esoteric interpretation of the Qur'an|interpretation]], in the sense of moving away from the literal meaning, is not justified. If a contradiction results from adopting the literal meaning, such as a literal understanding of the "hand" of God that contravenes his transcendence and the Qur'anic mention of his categorical difference from all other things, then an interpretation is warranted. In the above quote, Justice 'Abd al-Jabbar emphatically mentioned that if there are two possible interpretations, both capable of resolving the apparent contradiction created by literal understanding of a verse, then the interpretation closer to the literal meaning should take precedence, for the relationship between the interpretations, close and distant, becomes the same as the literal understanding and the interpretation.<ref name=":2" /> ===The first obligation=== Mu'tazilis believed that the first obligation on humans, specifically adults in full possession of their mental faculties, is to use their intellectual power to ascertain the existence of God, and to become knowledgeable of his attributes. One must wonder about the whole existence, that is, about why something exists rather than nothing. If one realises that there is a being who caused this universe to exist, not reliant on anything else and absolutely free from any type of need, then one realizes that this being is all-wise and morally perfect. If this being is all-wise, then his very act of creation cannot be haphazard or in vain. One must then be motivated to ascertain what this being wants from humans, for one may harm oneself by simply ignoring the whole mystery of existence and, consequently, the plan of the Creator. This paradigm is known in [[Kalam|Islamic theology]] as ''wujub al-nazar'', i.e., the obligation to use one's speculative reasoning to attain ontological truths. About the "first duty," ʿAbd al-Jabbar said it is "speculative reasoning (''al-nazar'') which leads to knowledge of God, because he is not known by the way of necessity (''daruratan'') nor by the senses (''bi l-mushahada''). Thus, he must be known by reflection and speculation."{{sfn|Martin|1997|page=90}} The difference between Mu'tazilis and other Muslim theologians is that Mu'tazilis consider ''al-nazar'' an obligation even if one does not encounter a fellow human being claiming to be a messenger from the Creator, and even if one does not have access to any alleged God-inspired or God-revealed scripture. On the other hand, the obligation of ''nazar'' towards other Muslim theologians is realized when encountering [[Prophet|prophets]] or [[Religious text|scripture]]. In this case, it was realized with the sending of the last prophet [[Muhammad]] and the last holy book, the [[Quran]]. In this way, the obligation to ''nazar'' is only carried out by studying the Quran and hadith of the prophet Muhammad, and also using the wisdom of the theologians and philosophers who followed him.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Kazanç |first=Fethi Kerim |date=2018-07-31 |title=An Overview of Knowledge-Value Relationship in Mu'tazilite Ethical Theory |url=https://zenodo.org/records/1488648 |journal=DergiPark |doi=10.5281/zenodo.1488648}}</ref> ===Reason and revelation=== [[File:Statue of Averroes (Córdoba) - BAE09705.jpg|thumb|[[Averroes]] insisted that all [[natural phenomena]] followed laws that God created.<ref name=Kadri-118>{{cite book|last1=Kadri|first1=Sadakat|title=Heaven on Earth: A Journey Through Shari'a Law from the Deserts of Ancient Arabia ...|date=2012|publisher=macmillan|isbn=9780099523277|pages=118–9|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=ztCRZOhJ10wC&q=Heaven+on+Earth%3A+A+Journey+Through+Shari%27a+Law|access-date=2020-10-27|archive-date=2020-12-27|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20201227213749/https://books.google.com/books?id=ztCRZOhJ10wC&q=Heaven+on+Earth%3A+A+Journey+Through+Shari%27a+Law|url-status=live}}</ref><ref name="Ghazali 2000, pp.116-7">For al-Ghazali's argument see ''The Incoherence of the Philosophers''. Translated by Michael E. Marmura. 2nd ed, Provo Utah, 2000, pp.116–7.</ref><ref name="For [[Ibn Rushd]] 2005, p.162">For Ibn Rushd's response, see Khalid, Muhammad A. ed. ''Medieval Islamic Philosophical Writings'', Cambridge UK, 2005, p.162)</ref>]] The Mu'tazilis had a nuanced theory regarding reason, Divine revelation, and the relationship between them. They celebrated [[reason|power of reason]] and [[intellect|human intellectual power]]. To them, it is the human intellect that guides a human to know God, his attributes, and the very basics of morality. Once this foundational knowledge is attained and one ascertains the truth of Islam and the Divine origins of the Qur'an, the intellect then interacts with scripture such that both reason and revelation come together to be the main source of guidance and knowledge for Muslims. Harun Nasution in the Mu'tazila and Rational Philosophy, translated in Martin (1997), commented on Mu'tazili extensive use of rationality in the development of their religious views saying: "It is not surprising that opponents of the Mu'tazila often charge the Mu'tazila with the view that humanity does not need revelation, that everything can be known through reason, that there is a conflict between reason and revelation, that they cling to reason and put revelation aside, and even that the Mu'tazila do not believe in revelation. But is it true that the Mu'tazila are of the opinion that everything can be known through reason and therefore that revelation is unnecessary? The writings of the Mu'tazila give exactly the opposite portrait. In their opinion, human reason is not sufficiently powerful to know everything and for this reason humans need revelation in order to reach conclusions concerning what is good and what is bad for them."{{sfn|Martin|1997|page=187}} The Mu'tazili position on the roles of reason and revelation is well captured by what [[Abu al-Hasan al-Ash'ari]] (died 324 AH/935 AD), the eponym of the Ashʿari school of theology, attributed to the Mu'tazili scholar [[Ibrahim an-Nazzam]] (died 231 AH/845 AD) (1969): {{Quote| كل معصية كان يجوز أن يأمر الله سبحانه بها فهي قبيحة للنهي، وكل معصية كان لا يجوز أن يبيحها الله سبحانه فهي قبيحة لنفسها كالجهل به والاعتقاد بخلافه، وكذلك كل ما جاز أن لا يأمر الله سبحانه فهو حسن للأمر به وكل ما لم يجز إلا أن يأمر به فهو حسن لنفسه ''No sin may be ordered by God as it is wrong and forbidden, and no sin shall be permitted by God, as they are wrong by themselves. To know about it and believe otherwise, and all that God commands is good for the ordered and all that it is not permissible except to order it is good for himself'' }} In the above formulation, a problem emerged, which is rendering something obligatory on the Divine being—something that seems to directly conflict with Divine omnipotence. The Mu'tazili argument is predicated on absolute Divine power and self-sufficiency, however. Replying to a hypothetical question as to why God does not do that which is ethically wrong (''la yaf`alu al-qabih''), 'Abd al-Jabbar replied:{{sfn|Martin|1997|page=96}} Because he knows the immorality of all unethical acts and that he is self-sufficient without them...For one of us who knows the immorality of injustice and lying, if he knows that he is self-sufficient without them and has no need of them, it would be impossible for him to choose them, insofar as he knows of their immorality and his sufficiency without them. Therefore, if God is sufficient without need of any unethical thing it necessarily follows that he would not choose the unethical based on his knowledge of its immorality. Thus every immoral thing that happens in the world must be a human act, for God transcends doing immoral acts. Indeed, God has distanced himself from that with his saying: "But Allah wills no injustice to his servants" (Qur'an 40:31), and his saying: "Verily Allah will not deal unjustly with humankind in anything" ([[Qur'an]] 10:44).<ref>{{Cite book |last=Vasalou |first=Sophia |url=https://philpapers.org/rec/VASMAA-2 |title=Moral Agents and Their Deserts: The Character of Mu'tazilite Ethics |date=2008 |publisher=Princeton University Press}}</ref><ref name=":1">{{Cite web |last=Abd al-Jabbār |first=Al-Qāḍī |title=Al-mughnī fī abwāb al-tawḥīd wa-l-ʿadl |url=https://albert.ias.edu/entities/publication/b795f609-3a80-4399-afcc-94c2f8c79eb8 |access-date=2024-12-15 |website=|doi=10.2143/MID.27.0.2036195 }}</ref> The thrust of ʿAbd al-Jabbar's argument is that acting immorally or unwisely stems from need and deficiency. One acts in a repugnant way when one does not know the ugliness of one's deeds, i.e., because of lack of knowledge, or when one knows but one has some need, material, psychological, or otherwise. Since [[God]] is absolutely self-sufficient (a result from the cosmological "proof" of his existence), all-knowing, and all-powerful, he is categorically free from any type of need and, consequently, he never does anything that is ridiculous, unwise, ugly, or evil.<ref name=":1" /> The conflict between Mu'tazilis and Ash'aris concerning this point was a matter of focus. Mu'tazilis focused on divine justice, whereas the Ashʿaris focused on divine omnipotence. Nevertheless, Divine self-restraint in Mu'tazili discourse is part of divine omnipotence, not a negation of it.<ref name=":0" /><ref>{{Cite web |title=Ash'ariyya and Mu'tazila - Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy |url=https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/ash-ariyya-and-mu-tazila/v-1# |archive-url=http://web.archive.org/web/20240803001911/https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/ash-ariyya-and-mu-tazila/v-1 |archive-date=2024-08-03 |access-date=2024-12-15 |website=www.rep.routledge.com |language=en}}</ref> ===Validity of hadith=== During the [[Abbasid]] dynasty, the poet, theologian, and jurist, [[Ibrahim an-Nazzam]] founded a [[madhhab]] called the Nazzamiyya that rejected the authority of Hadiths by [[Abu Hurayra]].<ref>{{cite book |last=Abdul-Raof |first=Hussein |date=2012 |title=Theological Approaches to Quranic Exegesis: A Practical Comparative-Contrastive Analysis |location=London |publisher=Routledge |pages=33–34 |isbn=978-0-41544-958-8}}</ref> His famous student, [[Al-Jahiz]], was also critical of those who followed such Hadiths, referring to his Hadithist opponents as ''al-nabita'' ("the contemptible").<ref>{{cite book |last=Zaman |first=Muhammad Qasim |date=1997 |title=Religion and Politics Under the Early 'Abbasids: The Emergence of the Proto-Sunni Elite |location=[[Leiden]] |publisher=[[E.J. Brill]] |page=55 |isbn=978-9-00410-678-9}}</ref> According to Racha El Omari, early Mu'tazilites believed that hadith were susceptible to "abuse as a polemical ideological tool"; that the ''[[matn]]'' (content) of the hadith—not just the ''isnad''—ought to be scrutinized for doctrine and clarity; that for hadith to be valid they ought to be ''[[mutawatir]]'', i.e. supported by ''tawātur'' or many ''[[isnād]]'' (chains of oral transmitters), each beginning with a different Companion.<ref>see: Ḍirār b. ʿAmr (died 728/815) In his al-Taḥrīsh wa-l-irjāʾ</ref><ref name="Ghani-65">{{cite book|last1=Ghani|first1=Usman|editor1-last=Duderija|editor1-first=Adis|title=The Sunna and its Status in Islamic Law: The Search for a Sound Hadith|date=2015|publisher=Springer |page=65|chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=9lamCwAAQBAJ&q=The+second+stance+consisted+of+accepting+a+report+if+it+was+supported+by+some+form+of+taw%C4%81tur&pg=PA65|access-date=29 March 2018|chapter=3. Concept of Sunna in Mu'tazilite Thought.|isbn=9781137369925|archive-date=14 October 2021|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20211014234228/https://books.google.com/books?id=9lamCwAAQBAJ&q=The+second+stance+consisted+of+accepting+a+report+if+it+was+supported+by+some+form+of+taw%C4%81tur&pg=PA65|url-status=live}}</ref> In writing about ''mutawatir'' (multi-isnād Hadith) and ''[[Ahaad|ahad]]'' (single-isnad hadith, i.e. almost all hadith) and their importance from the legal theoretician's point of view, [[Wael Hallaq]] notes the medieval scholar [[Al-Nawawi]] (1233–1277) argued that any non-''mutawatir'' hadith is only probable and can not reach the level of certainty that a ''mutawatir'' hadith can. However, these mutawir were extremely scarce. Scholars like [[Ibn al-Salah]] (died 1245 CE), al-Ansari (died 1707 CE), and Ibn ‘Abd al-Shakur (died 1810 CE) found "no more than eight or nine" hadiths that fell into the ''mutawatir'' category.<ref name=wael>{{cite journal |last=Hallaq |first=Wael |title=The Authenticity of Prophetic Ḥadîth: A Pseudo-Problem |journal=Studia Islamica |volume=89 |year=1999 |issue=89 |pages=75–90 |doi=10.2307/1596086 |jstor=1596086 |url-access=registration |url=http://almuslih.com/Library/Hallaq,%20W%20-%20The%20authenticity.pdf |access-date=30 March 2018 |archive-date=10 May 2016 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20160510232152/http://almuslih.com/Library/Hallaq,%20W%20-%20The%20authenticity.pdf |url-status=live }}</ref> [[Wasil ibn Ata|Wāṣil ibn ʿAṭāʾ]] (700–748 CE, by many accounts a founder of the Mu'tazilite school of thought), held that there was evidence for the veracity of a report when it had four independent transmitters. His assumption was that there could be no agreement between all transmitters in fabricating a report. Wāṣil's acceptance of tawātur seems to have been inspired by the juridical notion of witnesses as proof that an event did indeed take place. Hence, the existence of a certain number of witnesses precluded the possibility that they were able to agree on a lie, as opposed to the single report which was witnessed by one person only, its very name meaning the "report of one individual" (khabar al-wāḥid). Abū l-Hudhayl al-ʿAllāf (died 227/841) continued this verification of reports through tawātur, but proposed that the number of witnesses required for veracity be twenty, with the additional requirement that at least one of the transmitters be a believer.<ref name="Ghani-65"/> For Ibrahim an-Nazzam (c. 775 – c. 845), both the single and the mutawātir hadith reports as narrated by Abu Hurayra, the most prolific hadith narrater, could not be trusted to yield knowledge.<ref>{{Cite web |url=https://ore.exeter.ac.uk/repository/bitstream/handle/10036/4362/GhaniU.pdf?sequence=1&isAllowed=y |title=Archived copy |access-date=2020-12-12 |archive-date=2020-11-09 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20201109033912/https://ore.exeter.ac.uk/repository/bitstream/handle/10036/4362/GhaniU.pdf?sequence=1&isAllowed=y |url-status=live }}</ref> He recounted contradictory ḥadīth from Abu Hurayra and examined their divergent content (matn) to show why they should be rejected: they relied on both faulty human memory and bias, neither of which could be trusted to transmit what is true. Al-Naẓẓām bolstered his strong refutation of the trustworthiness of ḥadīths narrated by Abu Hurayra within the larger claim that his ḥadīths circulated and thrived to support polemical causes of various theological sects and jurists, and that no single transmitter could by himself be held above suspicion of altering the content of a single report. Al-Naẓẓām's skepticism involved far more than excluding the possible verification of a report narrated by Abu Hurayra, be it single or mutawātir. His stance also excluded the trustworthiness of consensus, which proved pivotal to classical Mu'tazilite criteria devised for verifying the single report (see below). Indeed, his shunning of both consensus and tawātur as narrated by Abu Hurayra earned him a special mention for the depth and extent of his skepticism.<ref>Racha El-Omari, "Accommodation and Resistance: Classical Muʿtazilites on Ḥadīth" in ''[[Journal of Near Eastern Studies]]'', Vol. 71, No. 2 (October 2012), pp. 234–235</ref> ===Atomism=== Mu'tazilite ideas of God were underpinned by the doctrine of atomism. This is the belief that all things and processes are reducible to fundamental physical particles and their arrangements. Mu'tazilite atomism however did not imply determinism. Since God was ultimately responsible for manipulating the particles, his actions were not bound by the material laws of the universe. This radically sovereign God entailed an occasionalist theology:<ref>RMaha Elkaisy-Friemuth, "God and Humans in Islamic Thought Abd Al-Jabbar", ''Ibn Sina and Al-Ghazali'', 2006</ref> God could intervene directly in the world to produce contingent events at will. This radical freedom was possible precisely because the world was composed solely of inert matter rather than an immaterial spirit with an independent vital force of its own.<ref>William Lane Craig, ''The Cosmological Argument from Plato to Leibniz'', 2001.</ref> ===Eschatology=== One of the "most sharply defined" issues where the Mu'tazila disagreed with "their theological opponents" was whether [[Jannah|Paradise]] and hell ([[Jahannam]]) had already been created or if their existence was waiting for [[Judgement Day]]. The "majority of the Mu'tazila rejected categorically" the idea that God had already created the Garden and the Fire on the grounds that "the physical universe does not allow for their existence yet". They also argued that because the Qur'an described everything in the universe except God being destroyed (the great ''fanāʾ'') "between the trumpet blasts" before Judgement Day, it would be more sensible to assume that the two abodes of the afterlife would be created after the great ''fanāʾ''<ref name=JISYYHIU1981:92>[[#JISYYHIU1981|Smith & Haddad, ''Islamic Understanding'', 1981]]: p.92</ref> A number of ḥadīth promise that viewing that face of God (''wajh Allah'') will be part of the reward of the faithful in paradise. However, the Mu'tazila, aside from their skepticism of ḥadīth, argued that if "God was an immaterial substance", as they believed he was, He was "by definition" not visible.<ref name=JISYYHIU1981:95>[[#JISYYHIU1981|Smith & Haddad, ''Islamic Understanding'', 1981]]: p.95</ref>
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)