Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
New riddle of induction
(section)
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
===Quine=== [[Willard Van Orman Quine]] discusses an approach to consider only "[[natural kind]]s" as projectible predicates.{{sfn|Quine|1970}} He first relates Goodman's grue paradox to [[Carl Gustav Hempel|Hempel]]'s [[raven paradox]] by defining two predicates ''F'' and ''G'' to be (simultaneously) projectible if all their shared instances count toward confirmation of the claim "each ''F'' is a ''G''".{{sfn|Quine|1970|p=41}} Then Hempel's paradox just shows that the complements of projectible predicates (such as "is a raven", and "is black") need not be projectible,{{efn|Observing a black raven is considered to confirm the claim "all ravens are black", while the [[contraposition|logically equivalent]] claim "all non-black things are non-ravens" is not considered to be confirmed by observing e.g. a green leaf.}} while Goodman's paradox shows that "is green" is projectible, but "is grue" is not. Next, Quine reduces projectibility to the subjective notion of ''similarity''. Two green emeralds are usually considered more similar than two grue ones if only one of them is green. Observing a green emerald makes us expect a similar observation (i.e., a green emerald) next time. Green emeralds are a ''natural kind'', but grue emeralds are not. Quine investigates "the dubious scientific standing of a general notion of similarity, or of kind".{{sfn|Quine|1970|p=42}} Both are basic to thought and language, like the logical notions of e.g. [[identity (philosophy)|identity]], [[negation]], [[disjunction]]. However, it remains unclear how to relate the logical notions to ''similarity'' or ''kind'';{{efn|Defining two things to be similar if they have all, or most, or many, properties in common doesn't make sense if properties, like [[mathematical set]]s, take things in every possible combination. {{sfn|Quine|1970|p=43}} Assuming a finite universe of ''n'' things, any two of them belong to exactly 2<sup>''n''-2</sup> sets, and share exactly that number of [[extensional]] properties. [[Satosi Watanabe|Watanabe]] called this the "[[Ugly duckling theorem]]".}} Quine therefore tries to relate at least the latter two notions to each other. {| style="float:right" | [[File:GoodmansCounterexampleNaturalKind.gif|thumb|150px|Goodman's counter-example against a definition of "natural kind" based on Carnap]] |} {| style="float:right" | [[File:Quine's qualitative sphere_svg.svg|thumb|150px|Failed attempt to define a kind as the set of all objects ''x'' that are more similar to a "paradigm" object ''p'' than ''p'' is to a "foil" object, in analogy to the definition of a [[circle]] area in geometry]] |} '''Relation between similarity and kind''' Assuming finitely many ''kinds'' only, the notion of ''similarity'' can be defined by that of ''kind'': an object ''A'' is more similar to ''B'' than to ''C'' if ''A'' and ''B'' belong jointly to more kinds{{efn|Rather than arbitrary sets}} than ''A'' and ''C'' do.{{sfn|Quine|1970|p=44}}{{efn|Quines uses this ternary relation in order to admit different levels of similarity, such that e.g. red things can be more similar to each other than just colored things.}} Vice versa, it remains again unclear how to define ''kind'' by ''similarity''. Defining e.g. the kind of red things as the set of all things that are more similar to a fixed "paradigmatical" red object than this is to another fixed "foil" non-red object (cf. left picture) isn't satisfactory, since the degree of overall similarity, including e.g. shape, weight, will afford little evidence of degree of redness.{{sfn|Quine|1970|p=44}} (In the picture, the yellow paprika might be considered more similar to the red one than the orange.) An alternative approach inspired by [[Carnap]] defines a natural kind to be a [[set (mathematics)|set]] whose members are more similar to each other than each non-member is to at least one member.{{sfn|Quine|1970|p=44-45}}{{efn|Formally: A set ''K'' is a kind if β''Y'' β ''K''. β ''X''<sub>1</sub> β ''K''. β ''X''<sub>2</sub> β ''K''. (''X''<sub>1</sub> is more similar to ''X''<sub>2</sub> than to ''Y'').}} However, Goodman{{sfn|Goodman|1951|p=163f}} argued, that this definition would make the set of all red round things, red wooden things, and round wooden things (cf. right picture) meet the proposed definition of a natural kind,{{efn|Each member of the set resembles each other member in being red, or in being round, or in being wooden, or even in several of these properties.}} while "surely it is not what anyone means by a kind".{{efn|The set contains e.g. yellow [[croquet]] balls and red rubber balls, but not yellow rubber balls.}}{{sfn|Quine|1970|p=45}} While neither of the notions of similarity and kind can be defined by the other, they at least vary together: if ''A'' is reassessed to be more similar to ''C'' than to ''B'' rather than the other way around, the assignment of ''A'', ''B'', ''C'' to kinds will be permuted correspondingly; and conversely.{{sfn|Quine|1970|p=45}} '''Basic importance of similarity and kind''' In language, every general term owes its generality to some resemblance of the things [[Reference#Semantics|referred]] to. [[Language acquisition|Learning]] to use a word depends on a double resemblance, viz. between the present and past circumstances in which the word was used, and between the present and past phonetic utterances of the word.{{sfn|Quine|1970|p=42, 45-48}} Every reasonable expectation depends on resemblance of circumstances, together with our tendency to expect similar causes to have similar effects.{{sfn|Quine|1970|p=42}} This includes any scientific experiment, since it can be reproduced only under similar, but not under completely identical, circumstances. Already [[Heraclitus]]' famous saying "No man ever steps in the same river twice" highlighted the distinction between similar and identical circumstances. {| align="right" class="collapsible collapsed" style="flush:right" |- ! colspan=2 | Birds' similarity relations |- valign="bottom" | [[File:Cooper's Hawk 2 edited.jpg|thumb|150px]] || [[File:Goose-flying.jpg|thumb|150px]] |- valign="top" | [[File:Falcon scheme of chickens and ducks.gif|thumb|150px]] || [[File:Goose scheme of chickens and ducks.gif|thumb|150px]] |- | colspan=2 width=300px | Tinbergen and Lorentz demonstrated a coarse similarity relation of inexperienced turkey chicks.{{sfn|Hoffman|1998|loc=Chapter 1}}{{sfn|Tinbergen|1951|loc=Chapter IV}}{{sfn|Tinbergen|1948|loc=p. 34, Fig. 21C}} '''Upper row:''' real hawk (left) and goose (right) in flight. '''Lower row:''' cardboard dummies releasing similar reactions as their originals. |} '''Genesis of similarity and kind''' In a [[Behaviorism|behavioral]] sense, humans and other animals have an innate standard of similarity. It is part of our animal birthright, and characteristically animal in its lack of intellectual status, e.g. its alienness to mathematics and logic,{{sfn|Quine|1970|p=46}} cf. bird example. ==== Habit formation ==== Induction itself is essentially [[Classical conditioning|animal expectation]] or habit formation. [[Ostensive definition|Ostensive learning]]{{sfn|Quine|1974|loc=Sect. 11}} is a case of induction, and a curiously comfortable one, since each man's spacing of qualities and kind is enough like his neighbor's.{{sfn|Quine|1970|p=47}} In contrast, the "brute irrationality of our sense of similarity" offers little reason to expect it being somehow in tune with the unanimated nature, which we never made.{{efn|Quine seems to allude to Vico's [[Giambattista Vico#The verum factum principle|verum factum principle]] here.}} Why inductively obtained theories about it should be trusted is the perennial philosophical [[problem of induction]]. Quine, following [[Satosi Watanabe|Watanabe]],{{sfn|Watanabe|1965|p=41}} suggests [[Charles Darwin|Darwin]]'s theory as an explanation: if people's innate spacing of qualities is a gene-linked trait, then the spacing that has made for the most successful inductions will have tended to predominate through [[natural selection]].{{sfn|Quine|1970|p=48}} However, this cannot account for the human ability to dynamically refine one's spacing of qualities in the course of getting acquainted with a new area.{{efn|Demonstrated by psychological experiments e.g. about classification of previously unseen artificial objects, like "[[Greeble (psychology)|Greebles]]".}}
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)