Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Admissible rule
(section)
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
==Variants== A '''rule with parameters''' is a rule of the form :<math>\frac{A(p_1,\dots,p_n,s_1,\dots,s_k)}{B(p_1,\dots,p_n,s_1,\dots,s_k)},</math> whose variables are divided into the "regular" variables ''p''<sub>''i''</sub>, and the parameters ''s''<sub>''i''</sub>. The rule is ''L''-admissible if every ''L''-unifier ''σ'' of ''A'' such that ''σs''<sub>''i''</sub> = ''s''<sub>''i''</sub> for each ''i'' is also a unifier of ''B''. The basic decidability results for admissible rules also carry to rules with parameters.<ref>Rybakov (1997), §6.1</ref> A '''multiple-conclusion rule''' is a pair (Γ,Δ) of two finite sets of formulas, written as :<math>\frac{A_1,\dots,A_n}{B_1,\dots,B_m}\qquad\text{or}\qquad A_1,\dots,A_n/B_1,\dots,B_m.</math> Such a rule is admissible if every unifier of Γ is also a unifier of some formula from Δ.<ref>Jeřábek (2005); cf. Kracht (2007), §7</ref> For example, a logic ''L'' is [[consistent]] iff it admits the rule :<math>\frac{\;\bot\;}{},</math> and a superintuitionistic logic has the [[disjunction property]] iff it admits the rule :<math>\frac{p\lor q}{p,q}.</math> Again, basic results on admissible rules generalize smoothly to multiple-conclusion rules.<ref>Jeřábek (2005, 2007, 2008)</ref> In logics with a variant of the disjunction property, the multiple-conclusion rules have the same expressive power as single-conclusion rules: for example, in ''S''4 the rule above is equivalent to :<math>\frac{A_1,\dots,A_n}{\Box B_1\lor\dots\lor\Box B_m}.</math> Nevertheless, multiple-conclusion rules can often be employed to simplify arguments. In [[proof theory]], admissibility is often considered in the context of [[sequent calculus|sequent calculi]], where the basic objects are sequents rather than formulas. For example, one can rephrase the [[cut-elimination theorem]] as saying that the cut-free sequent calculus admits the [[cut rule]] :<math>\frac{\Gamma\vdash A,\Delta\qquad\Pi,A\vdash\Lambda}{\Gamma,\Pi\vdash\Delta,\Lambda}.</math> (By abuse of language, it is also sometimes said that the (full) sequent calculus admits cut, meaning its cut-free version does.) However, admissibility in sequent calculi is usually only a notational variant for admissibility in the corresponding logic: any complete calculus for (say) intuitionistic logic admits a sequent rule if and only if ''IPC'' admits the formula rule that we obtain by translating each sequent <math>\Gamma\vdash\Delta</math> to its characteristic formula <math>\bigwedge\Gamma\to\bigvee\Delta</math>.
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)