Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Function composition
(section)
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
==Generalizations== [[Composition of relations|Composition]] can be generalized to arbitrary [[binary relation]]s. If {{math|''R'' β ''X'' [[cartesian product|Γ]] ''Y''}} and {{math|''S'' β ''Y'' Γ ''Z''}} are two binary relations, then their composition amounts to <math>R \circ S = \{(x,z) \in X \times Z: (\exists y \in Y)((x,y) \in R\,\and\,(y,z) \in S)\}</math>. Considering a function as a special case of a binary relation (namely [[Binary relation#Specific_types_of_binary_relations|functional relation]]s), function composition satisfies the definition for relation composition. A small circle {{math|''R''β''S''}} has been used for the [[Composition_of_relations#Notational_variations|infix notation of composition of relations]], as well as functions. When used to represent composition of functions <math>(g \circ f)(x) \ = \ g(f(x))</math> however, the text sequence is reversed to illustrate the different operation sequences accordingly. The composition is defined in the same way for [[partial function]]s and Cayley's theorem has its analogue called the [[WagnerβPreston theorem]].<ref name="Lipcomb_1997"/> The [[category of sets]] with functions as [[morphism]]s is the prototypical [[Category (mathematics)|category]]. The axioms of a category are in fact inspired from the properties (and also the definition) of function composition.<ref name="Hilton-Wu_1989"/> The structures given by composition are axiomatized and generalized in [[category theory]] with the concept of [[morphism]] as the category-theoretical replacement of functions. The reversed order of composition in the formula {{math|1=(''f''βββ''g'')<sup>β1</sup> = (''g''<sup>β1</sup> β ''f''β<sup>β1</sup>)}} applies for [[composition of relations]] using [[converse relation]]s, and thus in [[group theory]]. These structures form [[dagger category|dagger categories]].<blockquote>''The standard "foundation" for mathematics starts with [[Set theory|sets and their elements]]. It is possible to start differently, by axiomatising not elements of sets but functions between sets. This can be done by using the language of categories and universal constructions.'' ''. . . the membership relation for sets can often be replaced by the composition operation for functions. This leads to an alternative foundation for Mathematics upon categories -- specifically, on the category of all functions. Now much of Mathematics is dynamic, in that it deals with morphisms of an object into another object of the same kind. Such morphisms'' (''like functions'') ''form categories, and so the approach via categories fits well with the objective of organizing and understanding Mathematics. That, in truth, should be the goal of a proper philosophy of Mathematics.'' - [[Saunders Mac Lane]], [[Mathematics, Form and Function|Mathematics: Form and Function]]<ref>{{Cite web |title=Saunders Mac Lane - Quotations |url=https://mathshistory.st-andrews.ac.uk/Biographies/MacLane/quotations/ |access-date=2024-02-13 |website=Maths History |language=en}}</ref></blockquote>
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)