Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Knowledge
(section)
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
== Limits == The problem of the limits of knowledge concerns the question of which facts are [[Unknowability|unknowable]].<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Rescher|2009|pp=ix, 1–2}} | {{harvnb|Rescher|2005a|p=479}} | {{harvnb|Markie|Folescu|2023|loc=§ 1. Introduction}} }}</ref> These limits constitute a form of inevitable [[ignorance]] that can affect both what is knowable about the external world as well as what one can know about oneself and about what is good.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Markie|Folescu|2023|loc=§ 1. Introduction}} | {{harvnb|Rescher|2009|pp=2, 6}} | {{harvnb|Stoltz|2021|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=pTkqEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA120 120]}} }}</ref> Some limits of knowledge only apply to particular people in specific situations while others pertain to humanity at large.<ref>{{harvnb|Rescher|2009|p=6}}</ref> A fact is unknowable to a person if this person lacks access to the relevant information, like facts in the past that did not leave any significant traces. For example, it may be unknowable to people today what [[Caesar]]'s breakfast was the [[Ides of March|day he was assassinated]] but it was knowable to him and some contemporaries.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Rescher|2009|pp=2, 6}} | {{harvnb|Rescher|2009a|pp=140–141}} }}</ref> Another factor restricting knowledge is given by the limitations of the human [[Cognition|cognitive]] faculties. Some people may lack the cognitive ability to understand highly abstract mathematical truths and some facts cannot be known by any human because they are too complex for the human mind to conceive.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Rescher|2009|pp=10, 93}} | {{harvnb|Rescher|2009a|pp=x–xi, 57–58}} | {{harvnb|Dika|2023|p=163}} }}</ref> A further limit of knowledge arises due to certain logical [[paradox]]es. For instance, there are some ideas that will never occur to anyone. It is not possible to know them because if a person knew about such an idea then this idea would have occurred at least to them.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Rescher|2009|pp=3, 9, 65–66}} | {{harvnb|Rescher|2009a|pp=32–33}} | {{harvnb|Weisberg|2021|loc=§ 4. Fourth Case Study: The Limits of Knowledge}} }}</ref>{{efn|An often-cited paradox from the field of formal epistemology is [[Fitch's paradox of knowability]], which states that knowledge has limits because denying this claim leads to the absurd conclusion that every truth is known.<ref>{{harvnb|Weisberg|2021|loc=§ 4.2 The Knowability Paradox (a.k.a. the Church-Fitch Paradox)}}</ref>}} There are many disputes about what can or cannot be known in certain fields. [[Religious skepticism]] is the view that beliefs about God or other religious doctrines do not amount to knowledge.<ref>{{harvnb|Kreeft|Tacelli|2009|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=1DH1ZPyyTkIC&pg=PA371 371]}}</ref> [[Moral skepticism]] encompasses a variety of views, including the claim that [[Ethics#Moral knowledge|moral knowledge]] is impossible, meaning that one cannot know what is morally good or whether a certain behavior is morally right.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Sinnott-Armstrong|2019|loc=Lead Section, § 1. Varieties of Moral Skepticism, § 2. A Presumption Against Moral Skepticism?}} | {{harvnb|Sayre-McCord|2023|loc=§ 5. Moral Epistemology}} }}</ref> An influential theory about the limits of [[metaphysical]] knowledge was proposed by [[Immanuel Kant]]. For him, knowledge is restricted to the field of [[Phenomenon|appearances]] and does not reach the [[Thing in itself|things in themselves]], which exist independently of humans and lie beyond the realm of appearances. Based on the observation that metaphysics aims to characterize the things in themselves, he concludes that no metaphysical knowledge is possible, like knowing whether [[Kant's antinomies#The first antinomy (of space and time)|the world has a beginning or is infinite]].<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|McCormick|loc=§ 4. Kant's Transcendental Idealism}} | {{harvnb|Williams|2023|loc=Lead Section, § 1. Theoretical reason: reason’s cognitive role and limitations}} | {{harvnb|Blackburn|2008|p=101}} }}</ref> There are also limits to knowledge in the empirical sciences, such as the [[uncertainty principle]], which states that it is impossible to know the exact magnitudes of certain certain pairs of physical properties, like the position and [[momentum]] of a particle, at the same time.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Rutten|2012|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=8sHJD2fXDg4C&pg=PA189 189]}} | {{harvnb|Yanofsky|2013|pp=185–186}} }}</ref> Other examples are physical systems studied by [[chaos theory]], for which it is not practically possible to predict how they will behave since they are so sensitive to [[initial conditions]] that even the slightest of variations may produce a completely different behavior. This phenomenon is known as the [[butterfly effect]].<ref>{{harvnb|Yanofsky|2013|pp=161–164}}</ref> [[File:Philosopher,_marble_head,_Roman_copy,_AM_Corfu,_Krfm22.jpg|thumb|upright=.8|alt=Bust of Pyrrho of Elis|[[Pyrrho]] was one of the first philosophical skeptics.]] The strongest position about the limits of knowledge is [[radical skepticism|radical or global skepticism]], which holds that humans lack any form of knowledge or that knowledge is impossible. For example, the [[dream argument]] states that perceptual experience is not a source of knowledge since dreaming provides unreliable information and a person could be dreaming without knowing it. Because of this inability to discriminate between dream and perception, it is argued that there is no perceptual knowledge of the external world.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Windt|2021|loc=§ 1.1 Cartesian Dream Skepticism}} | {{harvnb|Klein|1998|loc=§ 8. The Epistemic Principles and Scepticism}} | {{harvnb|Hetherington|2022a|loc=§ 4. Sceptical Doubts About Knowing}} }}</ref>{{efn|A similar often-cited [[thought experiment]] assumes that a person is not a regular human being but a [[brain in a vat]] that receives electrical stimuli. These stimuli give the brain the false impression of having a body and interacting with the external world. Since the person is unable to tell the difference, it is argued that they do not know that they have a body responsible for reliable perceptions.<ref name="auto3">{{harvnb|Steup|Neta|2020|loc=§ 6.1 General Skepticism and Selective Skepticism}}</ref>}} This thought experiment is based on the problem of [[underdetermination]], which arises when the available evidence is not sufficient to make a rational decision between competing theories. In such cases, a person is not justified in believing one theory rather than the other. If this is always the case then global skepticism follows.<ref name="auto3"/> Another skeptical argument assumes that knowledge requires absolute certainty and aims to show that all human cognition is fallible since it fails to meet this standard.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Hetherington|2022a|loc=§ 6. Standards for Knowing}} | {{harvnb|Klein|1998|loc=§ 8. The Epistemic Principles and Scepticism}} | {{harvnb|Steup|Neta|2020|loc=§ 6.1 General Skepticism and Selective Skepticism}} }}</ref> An influential argument against radical skepticism states that radical skepticism is [[Self-refuting idea|self-contradictory]] since denying the existence of knowledge is itself a knowledge-claim.<ref>{{harvnb|Stroll|2023|loc=§ Skepticism}}</ref> Other arguments rely on [[common sense]]<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Steup|Neta|2020|loc=§ 6.2 Responses to the Closure Argument}} | {{harvnb|Lycan|2019|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=cfeEDwAAQBAJ&pg=PT21 21–22, 5–36]}} }}</ref> or deny that infallibility is required for knowledge.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|McDermid|2023}} | {{harvnb|Misak|2002|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=S6WHAgAAQBAJ&pg=PA53 53]}} | {{harvnb|Hamner|2003|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=Uno8DwAAQBAJ&pg=PA87 87]}} }}</ref> Very few philosophers have explicitly defended radical skepticism but this position has been influential nonetheless, usually in a negative sense: many see it as a serious challenge to any epistemological theory and often try to show how their preferred theory overcomes it.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Klein|1998|loc=§ 8. The Epistemic Principles and Scepticism}} | {{harvnb|Hetherington|2022a|loc=§ 4. Sceptical Doubts About Knowing}} | {{harvnb|Steup|Neta|2020|loc=§ 6.1 General Skepticism and Selective Skepticism}} }}</ref> [[Pyrrhonism|Another form of philosophical skepticism]] advocates the [[Epoche|suspension of judgment]] as a form of attaining [[Ataraxia|tranquility]] while remaining [[humility|humble]] and [[open-minded]].<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Attie-Picker|2020|pp=97–98}} | {{harvnb|Perin|2020|pp=[https://www.taylorfrancis.com/chapters/edit/10.4324/9781351168120-23/tranquility-goal-pyrrhonian-skepticism-casey-perin 285–286]}} }}</ref> A less radical limit of knowledge is identified by [[Fallibilism|fallibilists]], who argue that the possibility of error can never be fully excluded. This means that even the best-researched scientific theories and the most fundamental common-sense views could still be subject to error. Further research may reduce the possibility of being wrong, but it can never fully exclude it. Some fallibilists reach the skeptical conclusion from this observation that there is no knowledge but the more common view is that knowledge exists but is fallible.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Hetherington|loc=Lead Section, § 9. Implications of Fallibilism: Knowing Fallibly?}} | {{harvnb|Rescher|1998|loc=Lead Section}} | {{harvnb|Legg|Hookway|2021|loc=4.1 Skepticism versus Fallibilism}} }}</ref> [[Pragmatists]] argue that one consequence of fallibilism is that inquiry should not aim for truth or absolute certainty but for well-supported and justified beliefs while remaining open to the possibility that one's beliefs may need to be [[Belief revision|revised]] later.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Legg|Hookway|2021|loc=4.1 Skepticism versus Fallibilism}} | {{harvnb|Hookway|2012|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=_4KOTIyzMfwC&pg=PA39 39–40]}} }}</ref>
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)