Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Almost everywhere
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
{{Short description|Everywhere except a set of measure zero}} [[File:Function-1 x.svg|thumb|The function [[1/x]] is [[differentiable]] and [[Continuous function|continuous]] almost everywhere, more precisely, everywhere except at x = 0.]] In [[measure theory]] (a branch of [[mathematical analysis]]), a property holds '''almost everywhere''' if, in a technical sense, the set for which the property holds takes up nearly all possibilities. The notion of "almost everywhere" is a companion notion to the concept of [[measure zero]], and is analogous to the notion of ''[[almost surely]]'' in [[probability theory]]. More specifically, a property holds almost everywhere if it holds for all elements in a set except a subset of measure zero,<ref>{{Cite web|url=http://mathworld.wolfram.com/AlmostEverywhere.html|title=Almost Everywhere|last=Weisstein|first=Eric W.|website=mathworld.wolfram.com|language=en|access-date=2019-11-19}}</ref><ref>{{Cite book|url=https://archive.org/details/measuretheory00halm|title=Measure theory|last=Halmos|first=Paul R.|publisher=Springer-Verlag|year=1974|isbn=0-387-90088-8|location=New York}}</ref> or equivalently, if the set of elements for which the property holds is [[conull set|conull]]. In cases where the measure is not [[Complete measure|complete]], it is sufficient that the set be contained within a set of measure zero. When discussing sets of [[real number]]s, the [[Lebesgue measure]] is usually assumed unless otherwise stated. The term ''almost everywhere'' is abbreviated ''a.e.'';<ref>{{Cite web|url=https://www.dictionary.com/browse/almost-everywhere|title=Definition of almost everywhere {{!}} Dictionary.com|website=www.dictionary.com|language=en|access-date=2019-11-19}}</ref> in older literature ''p.p.'' is used, to stand for the equivalent [[French language]] phrase ''presque partout''.<ref>{{Cite journal|last=Ursell|first=H. D.|date=1932-01-01|title=On the Convergence Almost Everywhere of Rademacher's Series and of the BochnerfejΓ©r Sums of a Function almost Periodic in the Sense of Stepanoff|url=https://academic.oup.com/plms/article/s2-33/1/457/1523180|journal=Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society|language=en|volume=s2-33|issue=1|pages=457β466|doi=10.1112/plms/s2-33.1.457|issn=0024-6115}}</ref> A set with '''full measure''' is one whose complement is of measure zero. In probability theory, the terms ''almost surely'', ''almost certain'' and ''almost always'' refer to [[event (probability theory)|event]]s with [[probability]] 1 not necessarily including all of the outcomes. These are exactly the sets of full measure in a probability space. Occasionally, instead of saying that a property holds almost everywhere, it is said that the property holds for '''almost all''' elements (though the term [[almost all]] can also have other meanings). == Definition == If <math>(X,\Sigma,\mu) </math> is a [[measure space]], a property <math>P </math> is said to hold almost everywhere in <math>X </math> if there exists a measurable set <math>N \in \Sigma </math> with <math>\mu(N) = 0 </math>, and all <math>x\in X\setminus N </math> have the property <math>P </math>.<ref>{{Cite web|url=http://mathonline.wikidot.com/properties-that-hold-almost-everywhere|title=Properties That Hold Almost Everywhere - Mathonline|website=mathonline.wikidot.com|access-date=2019-11-19}}</ref> Another common way of expressing the same thing is to say that "almost every point satisfies <math>P\, </math>", or that "for almost every <math>x </math>, <math>P(x) </math> holds". It is ''not'' required that the set <math>\{x\in X: \neg P(x)\} </math> has measure zero; it may not be measurable. By the above definition, it is sufficient that <math>\{x\in X: \neg P(x)\} </math> be contained in some set <math>N </math> that is measurable and has measure zero. However, this technicality vanishes when considering a [[complete measure space]]: if <math>X</math> is complete then <math>N</math> exists with measure zero if and only if <math>\{x\in X: \neg P(x)\}</math> is measurable with measure zero. == Properties == * If property <math>P </math> holds almost everywhere and implies property ''<math>Q </math>'', then property ''<math>Q </math>'' holds almost everywhere. This follows from the [[Measure (mathematics)#Monotonicity|monotonicity]] of measures. * If <math> (P_n) </math> is a finite or a countable sequence of properties, each of which holds almost everywhere, then their conjunction <math> \forall n P_n </math> holds almost everywhere. This follows from the [[Measure (mathematics)#Measures of infinite unions of measurable sets|countable sub-additivity]] of measures. * By contrast, if <math> (P_x)_{x\in \mathbf R} </math> is an uncountable family of properties, each of which holds almost everywhere, then their conjunction <math> \forall x P_x </math> does not necessarily hold almost everywhere. For example, if <math>\mu </math> is Lebesgue measure on <math>X = \mathbf R </math> and <math> P_x </math> is the property of not being equal to <math> x </math> (i.e. <math> P_x(y) </math> is true if and only if <math> y \neq x </math>), then each <math> P_x </math> holds almost everywhere, but the conjunction <math> \forall x P_x </math> does not hold anywhere. As a consequence of the first two properties, it is often possible to reason about "almost every point" of a measure space as though it were an ordinary point rather than an abstraction.{{cn|reason=Give an example of this kind of reasoning.|date=April 2019}} This is often done implicitly in informal mathematical arguments. However, one must be careful with this mode of reasoning because of the third bullet above: universal quantification over uncountable families of statements is valid for ordinary points but not for "almost every point". == Examples == * If ''f'' : '''R''' β '''R''' is a [[Lebesgue integral|Lebesgue integrable]] function and <math>f(x) \ge 0 </math> almost everywhere, then <math display="block">\int_a^b f(x) \, dx \geq 0</math> for all real numbers <math>a < b </math> with equality [[if and only if]] <math>f(x) = 0</math> almost everywhere. * If ''f'' : [''a'', ''b''] β '''R''' is a [[monotonic function]], then ''f'' is [[derivative|differentiable]] almost everywhere. * If ''f'' : '''R''' β '''R''' is [[Lebesgue measurable]] and <math display="block">\int_a^b |f(x)| \, dx < \infty</math> for all real numbers <math>a < b </math>, then there exists a set ''E'' (depending on ''f'') such that, if ''x'' is in ''E'', the Lebesgue mean <math display="block">\frac{1}{2\varepsilon} \int_{x-\varepsilon}^{x+\varepsilon} f(t)\,dt</math> converges to {{math|''f''(''x'')}} as <math>\epsilon</math> decreases to zero. The set ''E'' is called the Lebesgue set of ''f''. Its complement can be proved to have measure zero. In other words, the Lebesgue mean of ''f'' converges to ''f'' almost everywhere. * A bounded [[function (mathematics)|function]] {{math|''f'' : [''a'', ''b''] β '''R'''}} is [[Riemann integral|Riemann integrable]] if and only if it is [[continuous function|continuous]] almost everywhere. * As a curiosity, the decimal expansion of almost every real number in the interval [0, 1] contains the complete text of [[Shakespeare's plays]], encoded in [[ASCII]]; similarly for every other finite digit sequence, see [[Normal number]]. == Definition using ultrafilters == Outside of the context of real analysis, the notion of a property true almost everywhere is sometimes defined in terms of an [[ultrafilter]]. An ultrafilter on a set ''X'' is a maximal collection ''F'' of subsets of ''X'' such that: # If ''U'' β ''F'' and ''U'' β ''V'' then ''V'' β ''F'' # The intersection of any two sets in ''F'' is in ''F'' # The empty set is not in ''F'' A property ''P'' of points in ''X'' holds almost everywhere, relative to an ultrafilter ''F'', if the set of points for which ''P'' holds is in ''F''. For example, one construction of the [[hyperreal number]] system defines a hyperreal number as an equivalence class of sequences that are equal almost everywhere as defined by an ultrafilter. The definition of ''almost everywhere'' in terms of ultrafilters is closely related to the definition in terms of measures, because each ultrafilter defines a finitely-additive measure taking only the values 0 and 1, where a set has measure 1 if and only if it is included in the ultrafilter. == See also == * [[Dirichlet function|Dirichlet's function]], a function that is equal to 0 almost everywhere. ==References== <references /> ==Bibliography== * {{cite book | last = Billingsley | first = Patrick | year = 1995 | title = Probability and measure | edition = 3rd | publisher = John Wiley & Sons | location = New York | isbn = 0-471-00710-2 }} {{Measure theory}} {{Lp spaces}} [[Category:Mathematical terminology]] [[Category:Measure theory]] [[ja:γ»γ¨γγ© (ζ°ε¦)#γ»γ¨γγ©θ³γγ¨γγγ§]]
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)
Pages transcluded onto the current version of this page
(
help
)
:
Template:Cite book
(
edit
)
Template:Cite journal
(
edit
)
Template:Cite web
(
edit
)
Template:Cn
(
edit
)
Template:Lp spaces
(
edit
)
Template:Math
(
edit
)
Template:Measure theory
(
edit
)
Template:Short description
(
edit
)