Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Combinatorial proof
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
In [[mathematics]], the term '''''combinatorial proof''''' is often used to mean either of two types of [[mathematical proof]]: * A proof by [[double counting (proof technique)|double counting]]. A [[combinatorics|combinatorial]] [[identity (mathematics)|identity]] is proven by counting the number of elements of some carefully chosen set in two different ways to obtain the different expressions in the identity. Since those expressions count the same objects, they must be equal to each other and thus the identity is established. * A [[bijective proof]]. Two sets are shown to have the same number of members by exhibiting a [[bijection]], i.e. a one-to-one correspondence, between them. The term "combinatorial proof" may also be used more broadly to refer to any kind of [[elementary proof]] in combinatorics. However, as {{harvtxt|Glass|2003}} writes in his review of {{harvtxt|Benjamin|Quinn|2003}} (a book about combinatorial proofs), these two simple techniques are enough to prove many theorems in combinatorics and [[number theory]]. ==Example== An archetypal double counting proof is for the well known formula for the number <math>\tbinom nk</math> of ''k''-[[combination]]s (i.e., subsets of size ''k'') of an ''n''-element set: :<math>\binom nk=\frac{n(n-1)\cdots(n-k+1)}{k(k-1)\cdots1}.</math> Here a direct bijective proof is not possible: because the right-hand side of the identity is a fraction, there is no set ''obviously'' counted by it (it even takes some thought to see that the denominator always evenly divides the numerator). However its numerator counts the [[Cartesian product]] of ''k'' finite sets of sizes ''n'', {{nowrap|''n'' − 1}}, ..., {{nowrap|''n'' − ''k'' + 1}}, while its denominator counts the [[permutations]] of a ''k''-element set (the set most obviously counted by the denominator would be another Cartesian product ''k'' finite sets; if desired one could map permutations to that set by an explicit bijection). Now take ''S'' to be the set of sequences of ''k'' elements selected from our ''n''-element set without repetition. On one hand, there is an easy bijection of ''S'' with the Cartesian product corresponding to the numerator <math>n(n-1)\cdots(n-k+1)</math>, and on the other hand there is a bijection from the set ''C'' of pairs of a ''k''-combination and a permutation ''σ'' of ''k'' to ''S'', by taking the elements of ''C'' in increasing order, and then permuting this sequence by ''σ'' to obtain an element of ''S''. The two ways of counting give the equation :<math>n(n-1)\cdots(n-k+1)=\binom nk k!,</math> and after division by ''k''! this leads to the stated formula for <math>\tbinom nk</math>. In general, if the counting formula involves a division, a similar double counting argument (if it exists) gives the most straightforward combinatorial proof of the identity, but double counting arguments are not limited to situations where the formula is of this form. Here is a simpler, more informal combinatorial proof of the same identity: :<math>\binom nk k!(n-k)!=n!</math> Suppose that n people would like to enter a museum, but the museum only has room for ''k'' people. First choose which ''k'' people from among the ''n'' people will be allowed in. There are <math>\tbinom nk</math> ways to do this by definition. Now order the ''k'' people into a single-file line so that they may pay one at a time. There are ''k''! ways to permute this set of size ''k''. Next, order the ''n'' − ''k'' people who must remain outside into a single-file line so that later they can enter one at a time, as the others leave. There are (''n'' − ''k'')! ways to do this. But now we have ordered the entire group of n people, something which can be done in ''n''! ways. So both sides count the number of ways to order the ''n'' people. Division yields the well-known formula for <math>\tbinom nk</math>. == The benefit of a combinatorial proof == <!-- Binomial coefficient links here --> {{harvtxt|Stanley|1997}} gives an example of a [[combinatorial enumeration]] problem (counting the number of sequences of ''k'' subsets ''S''<sub>1</sub>, ''S''<sub>2</sub>, ... ''S''<sub>''k''</sub>, that can be formed from a set of ''n'' items such that the intersection of all the subsets is empty) with two different proofs for its solution. The first proof, which is not combinatorial, uses [[mathematical induction]] and [[generating function]]s to find that the number of sequences of this type is (2<sup>''k''</sup> −1)<sup>''n''</sup>. The second proof is based on the observation that there are 2<sup>''k''</sup> −1 [[proper subset]]s of the set {1, 2, ..., ''k''}, and (2<sup>''k''</sup> −1)<sup>''n''</sup> functions from the set {1, 2, ..., ''n''} to the family of proper subsets of {1, 2, ..., ''k''}. The sequences to be counted can be placed in one-to-one correspondence with these functions, where the function formed from a given sequence of subsets maps each element ''i'' to the set {''j'' | ''i'' ∈ ''S''<sub>''j''</sub>}. Stanley writes, “Not only is the above combinatorial proof much shorter than our previous proof, but also it makes the reason for the simple answer completely transparent. It is often the case, as occurred here, that the first proof to come to mind turns out to be laborious and inelegant, but that the final answer suggests a simple combinatorial proof.” Due both to their frequent greater elegance than non-combinatorial proofs and the greater insight they provide into the structures they describe, Stanley formulates a general principle that combinatorial proofs are to be preferred over other proofs, and lists as exercises many problems of finding combinatorial proofs for mathematical facts known to be true through other means. ==The difference between bijective and double counting proofs== Stanley does not clearly distinguish between bijective and double counting proofs, and gives examples of both kinds, but the difference between the two types of combinatorial proof can be seen in an example provided by {{harvtxt|Aigner|Ziegler|1998}}, of proofs for [[Cayley's formula]] stating that there are ''n''<sup>''n'' − 2</sup> different [[tree (graph theory)|trees]] that can be formed from a given set of ''n'' nodes. Aigner and Ziegler list four proofs of this theorem, the first of which is bijective and the last of which is a double counting argument. They also mention but do not describe the details of a fifth bijective proof. The most natural way to find a bijective proof of this formula would be to find a bijection between ''n''-node trees and some collection of objects that has ''n''<sup>''n'' − 2</sup> members, such as the sequences of ''n'' − 2 values each in the range from 1 to ''n''. Such a bijection can be obtained using the [[Prüfer sequence]] of each tree. Any tree can be uniquely encoded into a Prüfer sequence, and any Prüfer sequence can be uniquely decoded into a tree; these two results together provide a bijective proof of Cayley's formula. An alternative bijective proof, given by Aigner and Ziegler and credited by them to [[André Joyal]], involves a bijection between, on the one hand, ''n''-node trees with two designated nodes (that may be the same as each other), and on the other hand, ''n''-node [[directed graph|directed]] [[pseudoforest]]s. If there are ''T<sub>n</sub>'' ''n''-node trees, then there are ''n''<sup>2</sup>''T<sub>n</sub>'' trees with two designated nodes. And a pseudoforest may be determined by specifying, for each of its nodes, the endpoint of the edge extending outwards from that node; there are ''n'' possible choices for the endpoint of a single edge (allowing self-loops) and therefore ''n<sup>n</sup>'' possible pseudoforests. By finding a bijection between trees with two labeled nodes and pseudoforests, Joyal's proof shows that ''T<sub>n</sub>'' = ''n''<sup>''n'' − 2</sup>. Finally, the fourth proof of Cayley's formula presented by Aigner and Ziegler is a [[Double counting (proof technique)#Counting trees|double counting proof due to Jim Pitman]]. In this proof, Pitman considers the sequences of directed edges that may be added to an ''n''-node [[empty graph]] to form from it a single rooted tree, and counts the number of such sequences in two different ways. By showing how to derive a sequence of this type by choosing a tree, a root for the tree, and an ordering for the edges in the tree, he shows that there are ''T<sub>n</sub>n''! possible sequences of this type. And by counting the number of ways in which a partial sequence can be extended by a single edge, he shows that there are ''n''<sup>''n'' − 2</sup>''n''! possible sequences. Equating these two different formulas for the size of the same set of edge sequences and cancelling the common factor of ''n''! leads to Cayley's formula. ==Related concepts== *The principles of double counting and bijection used in combinatorial proofs can be seen as examples of a larger family of [[combinatorial principles]], which include also other ideas such as the [[pigeonhole principle]]. *Proving an identity combinatorially can be viewed as adding more structure to the identity by replacing numbers by sets; similarly, [[categorification]] is the replacement of sets by categories. ==References== *{{citation | last1 = Aigner | first1 = Martin | last2 = Ziegler | first2 = Günter M. | author2-link = Günter M. Ziegler | pages = 141–146 | publisher = [[Springer-Verlag]] | title = [[Proofs from THE BOOK]] | year = 1998 | isbn = 3-540-40460-0}}. *{{citation | title = Proofs that Really Count: The Art of Combinatorial Proof | first1 = Arthur T. | last1 = Benjamin | author1-link = Arthur T. Benjamin | first2 = Jennifer J. | last2 = Quinn | author2-link = Jennifer Quinn | publisher = [[Mathematical Association of America]] | series = Dolciani Mathematical Expositions | volume = 27 | year = 2003 | isbn = 978-0-88385-333-7 | title-link = Proofs That Really Count }}. *{{citation | first = Darren | last = Glass | title = Read This: Proofs that Really Count | publisher = [[Mathematical Association of America]] | year = 2003 | url = http://www.maa.org/publications/maa-reviews/proofs-that-really-count}}. *{{citation|title=Enumerative Combinatorics, Volume I|first=Richard P.|last=Stanley|authorlink=Richard P. Stanley|series=Cambridge Studies in Advanced Mathematics|volume=49|publisher=Cambridge University Press|year=1997|isbn=0-521-55309-1|pages=11–12}}. [[Category:Enumerative combinatorics]] [[Category:Mathematical proofs]]
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)
Pages transcluded onto the current version of this page
(
help
)
:
Template:Citation
(
edit
)
Template:Harvtxt
(
edit
)
Template:Nowrap
(
edit
)